Skip to main content
Log in

Coherence, Probability and Explanation

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recently there have been several attempts in formal epistemology to develop an adequate probabilistic measure of coherence. There is much to recommend probabilistic measures of coherence. They are quantitative and render formally precise a notion—coherence—notorious for its elusiveness. Further, some of them do very well, intuitively, on a variety of test cases. Siebel, however, argues that there can be no adequate probabilistic measure of coherence. Take some set of propositions A, some probabilistic measure of coherence, and a probability distribution such that all the probabilities on which A’s degree of coherence depends (according to the measure in question) are defined. Then, the argument goes, the degree to which A is coherent depends solely on the details of the distribution in question and not at all on the explanatory relations, if any, standing between the propositions in A. This is problematic, the argument continues, because, first, explanation matters for coherence, and, second, explanation cannot be adequately captured solely in terms of probability. We argue that Siebel’s argument falls short.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See e.g. Douven and Meijs (2007), Fitelson (2003), Meijs (2006), Olsson (2002), Roche (2013), Schupbach (2011), and Shogenji (1999).

  2. For discussion of, and references regarding, the main probabilistic confirmation measures in the literature, see Crupi et al. (2007), Eells and Fitelson (2002), and Festa (1999).

  3. See Douven and Meijs (2007) for details on how to generalize from the case where A consists of two propositions to the case where A consists of n propositions.

  4. Swain’s complaint (about BonJour 1985) in the following passage is typical:

    One of the most disappointing features of BonJour’s book is the lack of detail provided in connection with the central notion of coherence. No effort is made at defining this concept. Instead, we are given several rather vaguely formulated conditions which loosely characterize coherence. (1989, p. 116)

    BonJour himself later notes that “the precise nature of coherence remains a largely unsolved problem” (1999, p. 124).

  5. See the references given in note 1. See also Koscholke (2013).

  6. The version of the argument given in Siebel (2011) is identical in all essential respects to the version given in Siebel (2005: 356–358). All subsequent references to Siebel are to Siebel (2011).

  7. Strictly speaking, Siebel appeals to a slightly different thesis: If H 1 explains D 1 and D 2, whereas H 2 explains only D 1, then, ceteris paribus, \( \left\{ {H_{1} ,D_{1} ,D_{2} } \right\} \) is more coherent than \( \left\{ {H_{2} ,D_{1} ,D_{2} } \right\} \). But Siebel (personal communication) does accept (1) and does hold that probabilistic measures of coherence run afoul of (1). What we say about (1) can be said mutatis mutandis about the slightly different thesis just mentioned. We focus on (1), and not on the slightly different thesis, in part because (1) is the simpler of the two theses.

  8. The same is true in cases where H 1 and H 2 confer on D a probability less than 1 (assuming there can be cases of this sort).

  9. It should also be noted that the Screening-Off Thesis is distinct from the considerably stronger thesis that explanatoriness is evidentially irrelevant; see Roche and Sober (2013) for discussion.

  10. See e.g. Harman (1986), Lycan (1988), and Thagard (1992).

  11. BonJour (1985, pp. 99–100) goes on to consider and reject the view that only explanatory relations are coherence-increasing.

  12. It might be countered that by definition a probabilistic coherence measure implies that any two sets having the same probability profile also have the same coherence value. Fine. The important point is that even if extant probabilistic coherence measures are false because they run counter to theses such as (1) and (2), there are coherence measures very much in the spirit of extant probabilistic coherence measures and on which two sets can have the same probability profile and yet differ in coherence because of differences concerning explanation. Such measures, as with extant probabilistic coherence measures, are quantitative and render formally precise the notion of coherence.

References

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1999). The dialectic of foundationalism and coherentism. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 117–142). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., & Tentori, K. (2012). A second look at the logic of explanatory power (with two novel representation theorems). Philosophy of Science, 79, 365–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., Tentori, K., & Gonzalez, M. (2007). On Bayesian measures of evidential support: Theoretical and empirical issues. Philosophy of Science, 74, 229–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Meijs, W. (2007). Measuring coherence. Synthese, 156, 405–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eells, E., & Fitelson, B. (2002). Symmetries and asymmetries in evidential support. Philosophical Studies, 107, 129–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Festa, R. (1999). Bayesian confirmation. In M. Galavotti & A. Pagnini (Eds.), Experience, reality, and scientific explanation (pp. 55–87). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (2003). A probabilistic theory of coherence. Analysis, 63, 194–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. In his Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 331–496). New York: Free Press.

  • Koscholke, J. (2013). Last measure standing: Evaluating test cases for probabilistic coherence measures, unpublished manuscript.

  • Lycan, W. (1988). Judgement and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meijs, W. (2006). Coherence as generalized logical equivalence. Erkenntnis, 64, 231–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. J. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth? Journal of Philosophy, 99, 246–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W. (2013). Coherence and probability: A probabilistic account of coherence. In M. Araszkiewicz & J. Savelka (Eds.), Coherence: Insights from philosophy, jurisprudence and artificial intelligence (pp. 59–91). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W., & Sober, E. (2013). Explanatoriness is evidentially irrelevant, or inference to the best explanation meets Bayesian confirmation theory. Analysis, 73, 659–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schupbach, J. N. (2011). New hope for Shogenji’s coherence measure. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 125–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schupbach, J. N., & Sprenger, J. (2011). The logic of explanatory power. Philosophy of Science, 78, 105–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (1999). Is coherence truth conducive? Analysis, 59, 338–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siebel, M. (2005). Against probabilistic measures of coherence. Erkenntnis, 63, 335–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siebel, M. (2011). Why explanation and thus coherence cannot be reduced to probability. Analysis, 71, 264–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain, M. (1989). BonJour’s coherence theory of justification. In J. Bender (Ed.), The current state of the coherence theory: Critical essays on the epistemic theories of Keith Lehrer and Laurence BonJour, with replies (pp. 115–124). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank Jakob Koscholke, Michael Roche, Mark Siebel, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments or discussion. This work was partly supported by Grant SI 173/1-1 to Mark Siebel from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) as part of the priority program “New Frameworks of Rationality” (SPP 1516).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Roche.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Roche, W., Schippers, M. Coherence, Probability and Explanation. Erkenn 79, 821–828 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9566-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9566-9

Keywords

Navigation