1 Introduction

The fundamental fairness principle of proportional representation is relevant in a variety of applications ranging from recommender systems to digital democracy [16]. It features most explicitly in the context of political elections, which is the language we adopt for this paper. In this context, proportional representation prescribes that the number of representatives championing an opinion in a legislature should be proportional to the number of voters who favor that opinion.

In most democratic institutions, proportional representation is implemented via what we call party-choice elections: Candidates are members of political parties and voters are asked to choose their favorite party; each party is then allocated a number of seats that is (approximately) proportional to the number of votes it received. The problem of transforming a voting outcome into a distribution of seats is known as apportionment. Analyzing the advantages and disadvantages of different apportionment methods has a long and illustrious political history and has given rise to an elegant mathematical theory [7, 48].

Forcing voters to choose a single party prevents them from communicating any preferences beyond their most preferred alternative. For example, if a voter feels equally well represented by several political parties, there is no way to express this preference within the voting system. In the context of single-winner elections, approval voting has been put forward as a solution to this problem as it strikes an attractive compromise between simplicity and expressivity [10, 40]. Under approval voting, each voter is asked to specify a set of candidates she “approves of,” i.e., voters can arbitrarily partition the set of candidates into approved candidates and disapproved ones. Proponents of approval voting argue that its introduction could increase voter turnout, “help elect the strongest candidate,” and “add legitimacy to the outcome” of an election [10,  pp. 4–8].

The practical and theoretical appeal of approval voting in single-winner elections has led a number of scholars to suggest to also use approval voting for multiwinner elections, in which a fixed number of candidates need to be elected [37]. Whereas, in the single-winner setting, the straightforward voting rule “choose the candidate approved by the highest number of voters” enjoys a strong axiomatic foundation [1, 14, 27, 28], several ways of aggregating approval ballots have been proposed for the multiwinner setting [37, 39].

Most studies of approval-based multiwinner elections assume that voters directly express their preference over individual candidates; we refer to this setting as candidate-approval elections. This assumption runs counter to widespread democratic practice, in which candidates belong to political parties and voters indicate preferences over these parties (which induce implicit preferences over candidates). In this paper, we therefore study party-approval elections, in which voters express approval votes over parties and a given number of seats must be distributed among the parties. We refer to the process of allocating these seats as approval-based apportionment.

Throughout this paper, we interpret a ballot that approves a set S of parties as a preference for legislatures with a larger total number of members from parties in S. This interpretation generalizes the natural interpretation of party-choice ballots as preferences for legislatures with a larger number of members of the chosen party. Our interpretation implicitly imputes perfect indifference between approved parties. This means that we assume voters to be indifferent to the distribution of seats between approved parties. For example, consider only legislatures with a fixed total number of seats given to approved parties. Then a voter would be indifferent between a legislature where the approved parties all get an equal number of seats, and a legislature where just one of the approved parties obtains all those seats. While this assumption is restrictive, it does allow for a simple voting process, and the additional expressivity of approval ballots compared to party-choice ballots seems attractive.

Indeed, we believe that party-approval elections are a promising framework for legislative elections in the real world, especially since allowing voters to approve multiple parties enables the aggregation mechanism to coordinate like-minded voters. For example, under party-choice elections, two groups of voters might vote for parties that they mutually disapprove of. Approval ballots could reveal that both groups approve a third party of more general appeal. Given this information, a voting rule could then allocate more seats to this third party, leading to mutual gain. This cooperation is particularly necessary for small minority opinions that are not centrally coordinated. In such cases, finding a commonly approved party can make the difference between being represented or votes being wasted because the individual parties receive insufficient support.

One aspect that makes it easier to transition from party-choice elections to party-approval elections (rather than to candidate-approval elections) is that party-approval elections can be implemented as closed-list systems. That is, parties can retain the power to choose the ordering in which their candidates are allocated seats, as they do in many current democratic systems. By contrast, candidate-approval elections necessarily confer this power to the voters (leading to an open-list system), which might give parties an incentive to oppose a change of the voting system. Of course, party-approval elections are compatible with an open-list approach, since we can run a secondary mechanism alongside the party-approval election to determine the order of party candidates.

1.1 Related work

To the best of our knowledge, this paper is the first to formally develop and systematically study approval-based apportionment. That said, several scholars have previously explored possible generalizations of existing aggregation procedures to allow for approval votes over parties.

For instance, Brams et al. [13] study multiwinner approval rules that are inspired by classical apportionment methods. Besides the setting of candidate approval, they explicitly consider the case where voters cast party-approval votes. They conclude that these rules could “encourage coalitions across party or factional lines, thereby diminishing gridlock and promoting consensus.”

Such desire for compromise is only one motivation for considering party-approval elections, as exemplified by recent work by Speroni di Fenizio and Gewurz [55]. To allow for more efficient governing, they aim to concentrate the power of a legislature in the hands of few big parties, while nonetheless preserving the principle of proportional representation. To this end, they let voters cast party-approval votes and transform these votes into a party-choice election by assigning each voter to one of her approved parties. Specifically, they propose to assign voters to parties so that the strongest party has as many votes as possible. We later call this method majoritarian portioning.

Several other papers consider extensions of approval-based voting rules to accommodate party-approval elections. In their paper introducing the satisfaction approval voting rule, Brams and Kilgour [11] discuss a variant of this rule adapted for party-approval votes. Mora and Oliver [41] and Camps et al. [20] study two approval-based multiwinner rules due to Phragmén and Eneström, and note that they also work for party-approval elections (which is true for any multiwinner rule using the embedding that we discuss in Sect. 3). Both papers consider a monotonicity axiom for party-approval elections (“if a party receives additional approvals, it should receive additional seats”) but find that their two methods fail it. For the case of two parties, they analyze the behavior of these rules as the house size approaches infinity. They find that both rules fail to converge to the most natural seat distribution. Janson and Öberg [34] analyze the limit behavior in more detail, and also show that Thiele’s sequential rule (aka SeqPAV) does converge to the ideal value.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Relations between the different settings of multiwinner elections. An arrow from X to Y signifies that X is a generalization of Y. The relationship corresponding to arrow (iii) has been explored by Brill et al. [18]. We establish and explore the relationship (i) in Sect. 3 and the relationship (ii) in Sect. 4

1.2 Relation to other settings

We can position party-approval elections between two well-studied voting settings (see Fig. 1).

First, our setting can be viewed as a special case of approval-based multiwinner voting, in which voters cast candidate-approval votes. A party-approval election can be embedded in this setting by replacing each party by multiple candidates belonging to this party, and by interpreting a voter’s approval of a party as approval of all of its candidates. This embedding establishes party-approval elections as a subdomain of candidate-approval elections (see arrow (i) in Fig. 1). In Sect. 3, we explore the axiomatic and computational ramifications of this domain restriction.

Second, approval-based apportionment generalizes standard apportionment (arrow (ii)), which corresponds to party-approval elections in which all approval sets are singletons (i.e., party-choice elections). In Sect. 4, we propose a method to generalize apportionment methods to the party-approval setting using so-called portioning methods.

1.3 Contributions

In this paper, we formally introduce the setting of approval-based apportionment and explore different possibilities of constructing axiomatically desirable aggregation methods for this setting. Besides its conceptual appeal, this setting is also interesting from a technical perspective.

Exploiting the relations described in Sect. 1.2, we resolve problems that remain open in the more general setting of candidate-approval elections. First, we show that the core of an approval-based apportionment problem is always nonempty, and that a popular multiwinner rule known as Proportional Approval Voting (PAV) always returns a core-stable committee. We also present a polynomial-time variant of PAV that is also core stable. Second, we prove that committee monotonicity is compatible with extended justified representation (a representation axiom proposed by Aziz et al. [3]) by providing a rule that satisfies both properties.

Some familiar multiwinner rules (in particular, PAV) provide stronger representation guarantees when applied in the party-approval setting. However, for many standard multiwinner voting rules, we give examples that show that their axiomatic guarantees do not improve in the party-approval setting. From a computational complexity perspective, we show that some rules known to be NP-hard in the candidate-approval setting remain NP-hard to evaluate in the party-approval setting. However, it becomes computationally easier to reason about proportionality axioms. Specifically, we show that it is tractable to check whether a given committee satisfies extended justified representation (or the weaker axiom of proportional justified representation). The analogs of these problems for candidate-approval elections are coNP-hard. These tractability results do not extend to checking whether a committee is core-stable: we show that this problem is coNP-complete for both party-approval and candidate-approval elections.

2 The model

A party-approval election is a tuple \((N,P,A,k)\) consisting of a set of voters \(N=\{1,\ldots ,n\}\), a finite set of parties \(P\), a ballot profile \(A=(A_1,\ldots ,A_n)\) where each ballot \(A_i \subseteq P\) is the set of parties approved by voter i, and the committee size \(k \in {\mathbb {N}}\). We assume that \(A_i \ne \emptyset \) for all \(i \in N\). When considering computational problems, we assume that k is encoded in unary (see Remark 3.1). This is a mild restriction since in most applications (such as legislative elections), k is smaller than the number of voters.

A committee in this setting is a multiset \(W: P\rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) over parties, which determines the number of seats \(W(p)\) assigned to each party \(p \in P\). The size of a committee W is \(|W|=\sum _{p \in P} W(p)\), and we denote multiset addition and subtraction by \(+\) and −, respectively. For a voter i and a committee W, we write \(u_i(W) = \sum _{p \in A_i} W(p)\) for the number of seats in W that are allocated to parties approved by voter i. A party-approval rule is a function that takes a party-approval election \((N,P,A,k)\) as input and returns a committee \(W\) of valid size \(|W| = k\).Footnote 1

In our axiomatic study of party-approval rules, we focus on two axioms capturing proportional representation: extended justified representation and core stability. Both are derived from their analogs in candidate-approval elections (see Sect. 3.2) where they were proposed by Aziz et al. [3]. To state these axioms, it is helpful to define the quota of a subset S of voters as \(q(S) = \lfloor k \cdot |S| / n \rfloor \). Intuitively, q(S) corresponds to the number of seats that the group S “deserves” to be represented by (rounded down).

Definition 2.1

A committee \(W: P\rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) provides extended justified representation (EJR) for a party-approval election \((N,P,A,k)\) if there is no subset \(S \subseteq N\) of voters such that \(\bigcap _{i \in S} A_i \ne \emptyset \) and \(u_i(W) < q(S)\) for all \(i \in S\).

In words, EJR requires that for every voter group S with a commonly approved party, at least one voter of the group must approve at least q(S) committee members. A party-approval rule is said to satisfy EJR if it only produces committees providing EJR.

We can obtain a stronger representation axiom by removing the requirement of a commonly approved party.

Definition 2.2

A committee \(W: P\rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) is core stable for a party-approval election \((N,P,A,k)\) if there is no nonempty subset \(S \subseteq N\) and committee \(T : P\rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) of size \(|T| \leqslant q(S)\) such that \(u_i(T) > u_i(W)\) for all \(i \in S\). The core of a party-approval election is the set of all core-stable committees.

Core stability requires adequate representation even for voter groups that cannot agree on a common party, by ruling out the possibility that the group can deviate to a smaller committee that represents all voters in the group strictly better. It follows from the definitions that core stability is a stronger requirement than EJR: If a committee violates EJR, there is a group S that would prefer any committee of size q(S) that assigns all seats to the commonly approved party.

Besides these representation axioms, a final axiom that we will discuss is committee monotonicity (e.g., [8, 24]). A party-approval rule f satisfies this axiom if, for all party-approval elections \((N, P, A, k)\), it holds that \(f(N, P, A, k) \subseteq f(N, P, A, k+1)\). The apportionment literature calls this house monotonicity. Committee monotonic rules avoid the so-called Alabama paradox, in which a party loses a seat when the committee size increases. They can also be used to construct proportional rankings [31, 53].

3 Constructing party-approval rules via multiwinner voting rules

In this section, we show how party-approval elections can be translated into candidate-approval elections. This embedding allows us to apply established candidate-approval rules to our setting. Exploiting this fact, we will prove the existence of core-stable committees for party-approval elections.

3.1 Preliminaries

A candidate-approval election is a tuple \((N, C, A, k)\). Just as for party-approval elections, \(N= \{1, \dots , n\}\) is a set of voters, \(C\) is a finite set, \(A\) is an n-tuple of nonempty subsets of \(C\), and \(k \in {\mathbb {N}}\) is the committee size. The conceptual difference is that \(C\) is a set of individual candidates rather than parties. This difference manifests itself in the definition of a committee because a single candidate cannot receive multiple seats. That is, a candidate committee W is now simply a subset of \(C\) with cardinality k. (Therefore, it is usually assumed that \(|C|\geqslant k\).) A candidate-approval rule is a function that maps each candidate-approval election to a candidate committee.

A diverse set of such voting rules have been proposed since the late 19th century [32, 37, 39], out of which we will only introduce the one which we use for our main positive result. Let \(H_j\) denote the jth harmonic number, i.e., \(H_j = \sum _{t=1}^{j} 1/t\). Given \((N, C, A, k)\), the candidate-approval rule proportional approval voting (PAV), introduced by Thiele [56], chooses a candidate committee W maximizing the PAV score \({\mathrm {PAV}}(W) = \sum _{i \in N} H_{|W \cap A_i|}\).

We now describe EJR and core stability in the candidate-approval setting, from which we derived our versions. Recall that \(q(S) = \lfloor k \, |S| / n \rfloor \). A candidate committee W provides EJR if there is no subset \(S \subseteq N\) and no integer \(\ell > 0\) such that \(q(S) \geqslant \ell \), \(|\bigcap _{i \in S} A_i| \geqslant \ell \), and \(|A_i \cap W| < \ell \) for all \(i \in S\). (The requirement \(|\bigcap _{i \in S} A_i| \geqslant \ell \) is often called cohesiveness.) A candidate-approval rule satisfies EJR if it always produces EJR committees.

The definition of core stability is even closer to the version in party-approval elections: A candidate committee W is core stable if there is no nonempty group \(S \subseteq N\) and no set \(T \subseteq C\) of size \(|T| \leqslant q(S)\) such that \(|A_i \cap T| > |A_i \cap W|\) for all \(i \in S\). The core consists of all core-stable candidate committees.

3.2 Embedding party-approval elections

We have informally argued in Sect. 1.2 that party-approval elections constitute a subdomain of candidate-approval elections. We formalize this notion by providing an embedding of party-approval elections into the candidate-approval domain. Our approach is similar to that of Brill et al. [18], who have formalized how apportionment problems can be phrased as candidate-approval elections.

For a given party-approval election \((N, P, A, k)\), we define a corresponding candidate-approval election \((N, C, A', k)\) with the same set of voters N and the same committee size k. The set of candidates contains k many “clone” candidates \(p^{(1)}, \dots , p^{(k)}\) for each party \(p \in P\), so \(C = \bigcup _{p\in P} \{p^{(1)}, \dots , p^{(k)}\}\). Voter i approves a candidate \(p^{(j)}\) in the candidate-approval election if and only if she approves the corresponding party p in the party-approval election. Thus, \(A_i' = \bigcup _{p \in A_i} \{p^{(1)}, \dots , p^{(k)}\}\).

A candidate committee \(W' \subseteq C\) corresponds to a committee \(W : P \rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) for the party-approval election with \(W(p) = |W' \cap \{ p^{(1)}, \dots , p^{(k)}\}|\). One can also convert in the other direction: a committee \(W : P \rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) for the party-approval election corresponds to the candidate committee \(W' = \bigcup _{p\in P} \{p^{(1)}, \dots , p^{(W(p))}\}\).

This embedding establishes party-approval elections as a subdomain of candidate-approval elections. As a consequence, we can apply rules from the more general candidate-approval setting to the party-approval setting, by

  1. 1.

    translating the party-approval election into a candidate-approval election,

  2. 2.

    applying the candidate-approval rule, and

  3. 3.

    converting its chosen candidate committee into a committee over parties.

Any axiom for candidate-approval rules implies an axiom for the derived party-approval rule. One can check that if a candidate-approval rule satisfies EJR or core stability (as defined in Sect. 3.1) then the derived party-approval rule satisfies the respective axiom (as defined in Sect. 2). In particular, note that by restricting our view to party approval, the cohesiveness requirement of EJR is reduced to requiring a single commonly approved party.

Remark 3.1

By our assumption that k is encoded in unary for the purpose of complexity analysis (see Sect. 2), the translation of a party-approval election yields a polynomial-sized candidate-approval election. Thus, a polynomial-time candidate-approval rule applied to the party-approval election runs in polynomial time as well. If k was instead encoded in binary, elections with large k and few parties could be described so concisely that even straightforward candidate-approval algorithms would formally have exponential running time.Footnote 2 (The same issue does not appear in candidate-approval elections, where we need to list at least k candidates, which makes the description verbose.)

In practice, rather than explicitly going via the embedding, it can be useful to write down the induced party-approval rule directly in terms of a party-approval election. For example, the party-approval version of PAV chooses a committee \(W: P \rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) that maximizes \({\mathrm {PAV}}(W) = \sum _{i\in N} H_{u_i(W)}\).

3.3 PAV guarantees core stability

A powerful stability concept in economics, core stability is a natural extension of EJR. It is particularly attractive because blocking coalitions do not need to unanimously approve any party; they only need to be able to coordinate for mutual gain.

Unfortunately, it is still unknown whether core-stable candidate committees exist for all candidate-approval elections.Footnote 3 All standard candidate-approval rules either already fail weaker representation axioms such as EJR, or are known to fail core stability. In particular, PAV satisfies EJR, but may produce non-core-stable committees for candidate-approval elections [3]. Peters and Skowron [43] show that a large class of candidate-approval rules (so-called welfarist rules) must all fail core stability.

For our main result, we show that core stability can always be achieved in the party-approval setting. Specifically, the committee selected by PAV is core stable for party-approval elections. Our proof uses a similar technique to the proof that PAV satisfies EJR for candidate-approval elections [3, Theorem 10]; we discuss the essential difference in Remark 3.4.

Theorem 3.2

For every party-approval election, PAV chooses a core-stable committee. Hence, the core of a party-approval election is nonempty.

Proof

Consider a party-approval election \((N,P,A,k)\) and let \(W_1: P \rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) be the committee selected by PAV. Assume for a contradiction that \(W_1\) is not core stable. Then there is a nonempty coalition \(S\subseteq N\) and a committee \(T : P\rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) such that \(|T| \leqslant q(S) \leqslant k \, |S| / n\) and \(u_i(T) \geqslant u_i(W_1) + 1\) for every voter \(i \in S\).

For each party p, we let \(\varDelta ^+(p, W_1)\) denote the marginal increase of the PAV score when we allocate an extra seat to p. Thus,

$$\begin{aligned} \varDelta ^+(p,W_1) = {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_1 + \{p\}) - {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_1) = \sum _{i \in N_p} \frac{1}{u_i(W_1) + 1}, \end{aligned}$$

where \(N_p =\{i \in N \mid p \in A_i\}\). Let us calculate the average marginal increase when adding an elements of T:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{|T|} \sum _{p \in P} T(p) \, \varDelta ^+(p, W_1)&= \frac{1}{|T|} \sum _{i \in N} \sum _{p \in A_i} \frac{T(p)}{u_i(W_1) + 1} \geqslant \frac{1}{|T|} \sum _{i \in S} \sum _{p \in A_i} \frac{T(p)}{u_i(W_1) + 1} \\&\geqslant \frac{1}{|T|} \sum _{i \in S} \sum _{p \in A_i} \frac{T(p)}{u_i(T)} = \frac{1}{|T|} \sum _{i \in S} \frac{u_i(T)}{u_i(T)} = \frac{|S|}{|T|} \geqslant \frac{n}{k}. \end{aligned}$$

Thus, there is a party \(p_1\) with \(\varDelta ^+(p_1,W_1) \geqslant n/k\). Let \(W_2 = W_1 + \{p_1\}\).

Next, for each party p with \(W_2(p) > 0\), let \(\varDelta ^-(p, W_2)\) be the marginal decrease of the PAV score if we take away a seat from p in \(W_2\). Thus,

$$\begin{aligned} \varDelta ^-(p,W_2) = {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_2)-{\mathrm {PAV}}(W_2 - \{p\}) = \sum _{i \in N_p} \frac{1}{u_i(W_2)}. \end{aligned}$$

The average marginal decrease of taking away a seat from \(W_2\) is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{k+1} \sum _{p\in P} W_2(p) \, \varDelta ^-(p,W_2)&= \frac{1}{k+1} \sum _{p\in P} \sum _{i \in N_p} \frac{W_2(p)}{u_i(W_2)} \\&= \frac{1}{k+1} \sum _{i \in N} \sum _{p \in A_i} \frac{W_2(p)}{u_i(W_2)} \\&= \frac{1}{k+1} |\{ i \in N : u_i(W_2) > 0 \}| \leqslant \frac{n}{k+1}. \end{aligned}$$

Thus, there is some party \(p_2\) with \(W_2(p_2) > 0\) such that \(\varDelta ^-(p_2, W_2) \leqslant \frac{n}{k+1}\). Write \(W_3 = W_2 - \{p_2\} = W_1 + \{p_1\} - \{p_2\}\). Then

$$\begin{aligned} {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_3)&= {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_2) - \varDelta ^-(p_2, W_2) \\&= {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_1) + \varDelta ^+(p_1,W_1) - \varDelta ^-(p_2, W_2) \\&\geqslant {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_1) + \tfrac{n}{k} - \tfrac{n}{k+1} \\&> {\mathrm {PAV}}(W_1), \end{aligned}$$

contradicting the optimality of \(W_1\). \(\square \)

Remark 3.3

Our proof of Theorem 3.2 can be easily adapted to show that PAV satisfies the stronger version of core defined with respect to the Droop quota [22, 33], by assuming \(|T| < (k + 1) |S|/n\) rather than \(|T| \leqslant k |S| / n\).

Remark 3.4

For candidate-approval elections, the proof of Theorem 3.2 shows that PAV satisfies core stability restricted to “disjoint objections”: if W is the committee selected by PAV, then there can be no set T with \(T \cap W = \emptyset \) such that there is a coalition S with \(T \leqslant q(S)\) and \(u_i(T) > u_i(W)\) for all \(i \in S\). Note that with our embedding of party-approval elections into candidate-approval elections, the disjointness assumption is without loss of generality if there are enough virtual candidates representing each party, and hence PAV satisfies core stability for party-approval elections. The disjoint objections property also implies the result of Peters and Skowron [43,  Theorem 6] that PAV satisfies the “2-core” property in the candidate-approval context: If there was an objection T that more than doubled the utility of each coalition member, then \(T \setminus W\) would be a disjoint core deviation, which is a contradiction.

Remark 3.5

Because \(H_j = {\varTheta }(\log {j})\), the PAV objective is closely related to the classical maximum Nash welfare (MNW) solution [36, 42]. One can see PAV as a discretization of the MNW solution for selecting a probability distribution \(\sigma : P \rightarrow [0,1]\) over parties, where we can interpret \(\sigma (p)\) as the fraction of seats that should be allocated to party p. That rule satisfies a continuous analog of the core condition [5, 25]. However, other natural discretizations of the Nash rule do not satisfy the core condition. In the next section, we will see that discretizing the Nash rule using common apportionment methods leads to violations of core stability. Furthermore, selecting a committee that maximizes Nash welfare (rather than the PAV objective function) may fail core stability, even in party-choice elections [18,  Theorem 2].

Given that PAV satisfies core stability in party-approval elections but not in candidate-approval elections, do other candidate-approval rules satisfy stronger representation axioms when restricted to the party-approval subdomain? We have studied this question for various rules besides PAV, and the answer was always negative; see Appendix B for details.Footnote 4

A major drawback of PAV is that it fails committee monotonicity, and PAV continues to fail this axiom in the party-approval setting.Footnote 5 Therefore, parties may lose seats when the committee size is increased. In the next section, we construct party-approval rules that avoid this undesirable behavior.

4 Constructing party-approval rules via portioning and apportionment

Party-approval elections are a generalization of party-choice elections, which can be thought of as party-approval elections in which all approval sets are singletons. Since there is a rich body of research on apportionment methods [7, 48] which act on party-choice elections, it is natural to examine whether we can employ these methods for our setting as well. To use them, we will need to translate party-approval elections into the party-choice domain on which apportionment methods operate. This translation thus needs to transform a collection of approval votes over parties into vote shares for each party. Motivated by time sharing, Bogomolnaia et al. [9] have developed a theory of such transformation rules, further studied by Duddy [23], Aziz et al. [5], and Brandl et al. [15]. We will refer to this framework as portioning.

The approach explored in this section, then, divides the construction of a party-approval rule into two independent steps: (1) portioning, which maps a party-approval election to a vector of parties’ shares; followed by (2) apportionment, which transforms the shares into a seat distribution.

Both the portioning and the apportionment literature have discussed representation axioms similar in spirit to EJR and core stability. For both settings, several rules have been found to satisfy these properties. One might hope that by composing two rules that are each representative, we obtain a party-approval rule that is also representative (and satisfies, say, EJR). If we succeed in finding such a combination, it is likely that the resulting voting rule will automatically satisfy committee monotonicity since most apportionment methods satisfy this property. In the general candidate-approval setting (considered in Sect. 3), the existence of a rule satisfying both EJR and committee monotonicity is an open problem [39].

4.1 Preliminaries

We start by introducing relevant notions from the literature on portioning [5, 9] and apportionment [7, 48], with notation suitably adjusted to our setting.

4.1.1 Portioning

A portioning problem is a triple \((N, P, A)\), just as in party-approval voting but without a committee size. A portioning is a function \(r: P \rightarrow [0,1]\) with \(\sum _{p \in P} r(p)=1\). We interpret r(p) as the vote share of party p. A portioning method maps each portioning problem \((N, P, A)\) to a portioning.

Our minimum requirement on portioning methods will be that they uphold proportionality if all approval sets are singletons, i.e., if we are already in the party-choice domain. Formally, we say that a portioning method is faithful if for all \((N, P, A)\) with \(|A_i|=1\) for all \(i \in N\), the resulting portioning r satisfies \(r(p) = |\{i \in N\mid A_i = \{p\}\}| / n\) for all \(p \in P\). Among the portioning methods considered by Aziz et al. [5], only three are faithful. They are defined as follows.

  • Conditional utilitarian portioning selects, for each voter i, \(p_i\) as a party in \(A_i\) approved by the highest number of voters. Then, \(r(p) = |\{i \in N \mid p_i = p\}| / n\) for all \(p \in P\).

  • Random priority computes n! portionings, one for each permutation \(\sigma \) of N, and returns their average. The portioning for \(\sigma = (i_1, \dots , i_n)\) maximizes \(\sum _{p \in A_{i_1}}\! r(p)\), breaking ties by maximizing \(\sum _{p \in A_{i_2}}\! r(p)\), and so forth.

  • Nash portioning selects the portioning r maximizing the Nash welfare \(\prod _{i \in N} \big ( \sum _{p \in A_i} \! r(p) \big )\).

When computing the outcomes of these rules, ties may occur. For our results it will not matter how ties are broken: we only use these rules in counterexamples in which no ties occur.

On first sight, Nash portioning seems particularly promising because it satisfies portioning versions of core stability and EJR [5, 30]. Concretely, it satisfies a property called average fair share introduced by Aziz et al. [5], which requires that there is no subset \(S\subseteq N\) of voters such that \(\bigcap _{i \in S} A_i \ne \emptyset \) and \(\frac{1}{|S|}\sum _{i\in S}\sum _{p \in A_i} r(p) < |S|/|N|\). However, despite these promising properties, we will see that Nash portioning does not work for our purposes. Instead, we will need to make use of a more recent portioning approach, which was proposed by Speroni di Fenizio and Gewurz [55] in the context of party-approval voting.

  • Majoritarian portioning proceeds in rounds \(j = 1, 2, \dots \). Initially, all parties and voters are active. In iteration j, select the active party \(p_j\) that is approved by the highest number of active voters. Let \(N_j\) be the set of active voters who approve \(p_j\). Then, set \(r(p_j)\) to \(|N_j| / n\), and mark \(p_j\) and all voters in \(N_j\) as inactive. If active voters remain, start the next iteration; otherwise, return r.

Under majoritarian portioning, we ignore the approval preferences of voters after they have been “assigned” to a party. Note that conditional utilitarian portioning is a similar sequential method which does, however, not ignore the preferences of inactive voters.

4.1.2 Apportionment

An apportionment problem is a tuple \((P, r, k)\), which consists of a finite set of parties \(P\), a portioning \(r : P\rightarrow [0, 1]\) specifying the vote shares of parties, and a committee size \(k \in {\mathbb {N}}\). Committees are defined as for party-approval elections, and an apportionment method maps apportionment problems to committees \(W\) of size k.

An apportionment method satisfies lower quota if each party p is always allocated at least \(\lfloor k \cdot r(p) \rfloor \) seats in the committee. Furthermore, an apportionment method f is committee monotonic if \(f(P, r, k) \subseteq f(P, r, k + 1)\) for every apportionment problem \((P, r, k)\).

Among the standard apportionment methods, only two satisfy both lower quota and committee monotonicity: the D’Hondt method (aka Jefferson method) and the quota method.Footnote 6 The D’Hondt method assigns the k seats iteratively, each time giving the next seat to the party p with the largest quotient \(r(p)/(s(p)+1)\), where s(p) denotes the number of seats already assigned to p. The quota method [6] is identical to the D’Hondt method, except that, in the jth iteration, only parties p satisfying \(s(p)/j<r(p)\) are eligible for the allocation of the next seat. Ties should be broken in a consistent fashion so as to ensure house monotonicity, for example using a fixed tie-breaking order over parties.

4.1.3 Composition

If we take any portioning method and any apportionment method, we can compose them to obtain a party-approval rule. Formally, the composition of portioning method R and apportionment method M maps each party-approval election (NPAk) to a committee M(PR(NPA), k). Note that if the apportionment method is committee monotonic then so is the composed rule, since the portioning is independent of k.

4.2 Composed rules that fail EJR

Perhaps surprisingly, many pairs of portioning and apportionment methods fail EJR. This is certainly true if the individual parts are not representative themselves. For example, if an apportionment method M “properly” fails lower quota (in the sense that there is a rational-valued input r on which lower quota is violated), then one can construct an example profile on which any composed rule using M fails EJR: Construct a party-approval election with singleton approval sets in which the voter counts are proportional to the shares in the counterexample r. Then any faithful portioning method, applied to this election, must return r. Since M fails lower quota on r, the resulting committee will violate EJR. By a similar argument, suppose that an apportionment method violates committee monotonicity, and that there is a rational-valued counterexample. Then the apportionment method, when composed with a faithful portioning method, will give rise to a party-approval rule that fails committee monotonicity.

As mentioned above, D’Hondt and the quota method are the only standard apportionment rules to satisfy both lower quota and committee monotonicity. However, the composition of either option with the conditional utilitarian, random priority, or Nash portioning methods fails EJR, as the following examples show.

Example 4.1

Let \(n = k = 6\), \(P= \{p_0, p_1, p_2, p_3\}\), and consider the ballot profile \(A= (\{p_0\}, \{p_0\}, \{p_0, p_1, p_2\}, \{p_0, p_1, p_2\}, \{p_1, p_3\}, \{p_2, p_3\})\).

Then, the conditional utilitarian solution sets \(r(p_0) = 4/6\), \(r(p_1) = r(p_2) = 1/6\), and \(r(p_3) = 0\). Any apportionment method satisfying lower quota allocates four seats to \(p_0\), one each to \(p_1\) and \(p_2\), and none to \(p_3\). The resulting committee does not provide EJR since the last two voters, who jointly approve \(p_3\), have a quota of \(q(\{5,6\})=2\) that is not met. \(\square \)

Example 4.2

Let \(n = k = 6\), \(P= \{p_0, p_1, p_2, p_3\}\), and consider the ballot profile \(A= (\{p_0\}, \{p_0\}, \{p_0, p_1, p_2\}, \{p_0, p_1, p_3\}, \{p_1\}, \{p_2, p_3\})\).

Random priority chooses the portioning \(r(p_0) = 23/45\), \(r(p_1) = 23/90\), and \(r(p_2) = r(p_3) = 7/60\). Both D’Hondt and the quota method allocate four seats to \(p_0\), two seats to \(p_1\), and none to the other two parties. This violates the claim to representation of the sixth voter (with \(q(\{6\})=1\)).

Nash portioning produces a fairly similar portioning, with \(r(p_0) \approx 0.5302\), \(r(p_1) \approx 0.2651\), and \(r(p_2) = r(p_3) \approx 0.1023\). D’Hondt and the quota method produce the same committee as above, leading to the same EJR violation. \(\square \)

It might be surprising that Nash portioning combined with a lower-quota apportionment method violates EJR. After all, Nash portioning satisfies core stability in the portioning setting, which is a strong notion of proportionality, and the lower-quota property limits the rounding losses when moving from the portioning to a committee. As expected, in the election of Example 4.2, the portioning produced by Nash gives sufficient representation to the sixth voter since \(r(p_2) + r(p_3) \approx 0.2047 > 1/6\). However, since both \(r(p_2)\) and \(r(p_3)\) are below 1/6 on their own, lower quota does not apply to either of the two parties, and the sixth voter loses all representation in the apportionment step.Footnote 7

4.3 Composed rules that satisfy EJR

As we have seen, several initially promising portioning methods fail to compose to a rule that satisfies EJR. One reason is that these portioning methods are happy to assign small shares to several parties. The apportionment method may round several of those small shares down to zero seats. This can lead to a failure of EJR when not enough parties obtain a seat. It is difficult for an apportionment method to avoid this behavior since the portioning step obscures the relationships between different parties that are apparent from the approval ballots of the voters.

Since majoritarian portioning maximizes the seat allocations to the largest parties, it tends to avoid the problem we have just identified. While it fails the strong representation axioms that Nash portioning satisfies, this turns out not to be crucial: Composing majoritarian portioning with any apportionment method satisfying lower quota yields an EJR rule. If we use an apportionment method that is also committee monotonic, such as D’Hondt or the quota method, we obtain a party-approval rule that satisfies both EJR and committee monotonicity.

Theorem 4.3

Let M be a committee monotonic apportionment method satisfying lower quota. Then, the party-approval rule composing majoritarian portioning and M satisfies EJR and committee monotonicity.

Proof

Consider a party-approval election (NPAk) and let r be the outcome of majoritarian portioning applied to (NPA). Let \(N_1, N_2, \dots \) and \(p_1, p_2, \dots \) be the voter groups and parties in the construction of majoritarian portioning, so that \(r(p_j) = |N_j|/n\) for all j.

Consider the committee \(W = M(P,r,k)\) and suppose that EJR is violated, i.e., that there exists a group \(S \subseteq N\) with \(\bigcap _{i \in S} A_i \ne \emptyset \) and \(u_i(W) < q(S)\) for all \(i \in S\).

Let j be minimal such that \(S \cap N_j \ne \emptyset \). We now show that \(|S| \leqslant |N_j|\). By the definition of j, no voter in S approves of any of the parties \(p_1, p_2, \dots p_{j-1}\); thus, all those voters remain active in round j. Consider a party \(p^* \in \bigcap _{i \in S} A_i\). In the jth iteration of majoritarian portioning, this party had an approval score (among active voters) of at least |S|. Therefore, the party \(p_j\) chosen in the jth iteration has an approval score that is at least |S| (of course, \(p^* = p_j\) is possible). The approval score of party \(p_j\) equals \(|N_j|\). Therefore, \(|N_j| \geqslant |S|\).

Since \(|N_j| \geqslant |S|\), we have \(q(N_j)\geqslant q(S)\). Since M satisfies lower quota, it assigns at least \(\lfloor k \cdot r(p_j) \rfloor = \lfloor k \, (|N_j|/n) \rfloor = q(N_j)\) seats to party \(p_j\). Now consider a voter \(i \in S \cap N_j\). Since this voter approves party \(p_j\), we have \(u_i(W) \geqslant W(p_j) \geqslant q(N_j) \geqslant q(S)\), a contradiction.

This shows that EJR is indeed satisfied; committee monotonicity follows from the committee monotonicity of M. \(\square \)

While the party-approval rules identified by Theorem 4.3 satisfy EJR and committee monotonicity, they do not reach our gold standard of representation, i.e., core stability:

Example 4.4

Let \(n = k = 16\), \(P = \{p_0, \dots , p_4\}\), and consider the following ballot profile:

$$\begin{aligned}&4 \times \{p_0, p_1\}, \qquad 3 \times \{p_1, p_2\}, \qquad 1 \times \{p_2\} \\&4 \times \{p_0, p_3\}, \qquad 3 \times \{p_3, p_4\}, \qquad 1 \times \{p_4\} \end{aligned}$$

Majoritarian portioning allocates 1/2 to \(p_0\) and 1/4 each to \(p_2\) and \(p_4\). Any lower-quota apportionment method must translate this into 8 seats for \(p_0\) and 4 seats each for \(p_2\) and \(p_4\). This committee is not in the core: Let S be the coalition of all 14 voters who approve multiple parties, and let T allocate 4 seats to \(p_0\) and 5 seats each to \(p_1\) and \(p_3\). This gives strictly higher representation to all members of the coalition. \(\square \)

The example makes it obvious why majoritarian portioning cannot satisfy core stability: All voters approving of \(p_0\) get deactivated after the first round, which makes \(p_2\) seem universally preferable to \(p_1\). However, \(p_1\) is a useful vehicle for cooperation between the group approving \(\{p_0, p_1\}\) and the group approving \(\{p_1, p_2\}\). Since majoritarian portioning is blind to this opportunity, it cannot guarantee core stability.

The example also illustrates the power of core stability: The deviating coalition does not agree on any single party they support, but would nonetheless benefit from the deviation. Core stability is sensitive to this demand for better representation.

5 Computational aspects

To use a voting rule, we need to compute its output. Ideally, we would like an efficient (i.e., polynomial-time) algorithm for this task, so that we can announce the voting outcome soon after all votes have been cast. Fortunately, many rules admit fast algorithms. For example, the composed rules from Sect. 4.3 can be computed efficiently as long as the employed portioning and apportionment methods are computable in polynomial time (which is the case for majoritarian portioning as well as for D’Hondt and the quota method). In addition, by our discussion in Remark 3.1, every multiwinner voting rule that runs in polynomial time for the candidate-approval setting also runs in polynomial time for the party-approval setting.

That being said, given our result about core stability in Sect. 3, we are particularly interested in computing the outcome of PAV, which is NP-hard to compute in the candidate-approval setting [2]. Since party-approval elections are a restricted domain, it is in principle possible that PAV is easier to compute on that domain, but, as we show in Appendix A, hardness still holds for party-approval elections.

Theorem 5.1

For a given party-approval election and threshold \(s \in {\mathbb {R}}\), deciding whether there exists a committee with PAV score at least s is NP-hard.

Equally confronted with the computational complexity of PAV, Aziz et al. [4] proposed a local-search variant of PAV, which runs in polynomial time and guarantees EJR in the candidate-approval setting. Using the same approach, we can find a core-stable committee in the party-approval setting.

Theorem 5.2

Given a party-approval election, a core-stable committee can be computed in polynomial time.

We defer the proof of this theorem to Appendix A. In Appendix B.1, we additionally show that an optimization variant of Phragmén ’s rule [17] remains intractable in the party-approval subdomain.

Lackner and Skowron [39] posed as an open problem to determine the complexity of checking whether a given committee satisfies core stability. We show that the problem is coNP-complete. Our proof is written for party-approval elections, but the result implies hardness for the candidate-approval setting because party-approval elections are a special case of candidate-approval elections.

Theorem 5.3

For a given party-approval (or candidate-approval) election and a committee W, it is coNP-complete to decide whether W satisfies core stability.

Proof

The complement problem is clearly in NP since a core deviation provides a certificate. We reduce from the NP-complete problem exact cover by 3-sets (X3C). Here, given a set X with \(|X| = 3r\) and a collection \({\mathcal {B}}\) of 3-element subsets of X, the question is whether there exists a selection \({\mathcal {B}}' \subseteq {\mathcal {B}}\) of r of the subsets such that every element of X occurs in one of the sets in \({\mathcal {B}}'\).

We construct an instance of our problem as follows: For every set \(B \in {\mathcal {B}}\) we introduce a set candidate and for every element in X we introduce an element voter. We set \(k=r\) and introduce one special voter, \(k-1\) private candidates and one dummy candidate. The approval sets are as follows: Each element voter \(x \in X\) approves exactly those set candidates \(B \in {\mathcal {B}}\) with \(x \in B\) and the special voter approves all candidates except the dummy candidate. (Thus, no voter approves the dummy candidate.) Finally, let W be the committee consisting of the private candidates and the dummy candidate.Footnote 8 Note that \(|W| = k\). We claim that W is not core stable if and only if the X3C instance is a yes instance.

Suppose that W is not core stable, and let \(S \subseteq N\) and committee \(T : P \rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\) witness this fact. Without loss of generality, we may assume that T only gives seats to set candidates, since all other candidates are dominated by set candidates. Suppose \(|T| = t\). Then T provides positive utility to at most 3t element voters. These 3t voters on their own can afford \(\lfloor 3t \cdot k / n \rfloor \leqslant 3t \cdot k / (3k + 1) < t\) candidates. Because all element voters in S must obtain positive utility from T, it follows that the special voter must be part of S. Because the special voter i has \(u_i(T) > u_i(W) = k - 1\), we have \(u_i(T) = k\). Thus \(|T| = k\), and a committee of this size can only be afforded by the grand coalition, so \(S = N\). Thus, every element voter is part of S and thus obtains positive utility from T, and hence for every element, T contains at least one set candidate corresponding to a set containing that element. It follows that the X3C instance has a solution.

Conversely, every solution to the X3C instance induces a committee T consisting of the k set candidates chosen by the solution. Then T gives positive utility to all element voters and increases the special voter’s utility from \(k-1\) to k. Hence T together with \(S = N\) show that W is not core stable. \(\square \)

In the candidate-approval setting, checking whether a given committee satisfies EJR is coNP-complete [3, 4]. In other words, given a committee, it is hard to find a cohesive coalition of voters that is underrepresented. Interestingly, this task is tractable in party-approval elections. Intuitively, checking becomes easier in party-approval elections as groups of voters are already cohesive when they have only a single approved party in common.

Theorem 5.4

Given a party-approval election \((N,P,A,k)\) and a committee \(W: P\rightarrow {\mathbb {N}}\), it can be checked in polynomial time whether \(W\) satisfies EJR.

Proof

We describe a procedure to check whether a given committee \(W\) violates EJR. For each party \(p \in P\) and each \(\ell \in [k]\), define

$$\begin{aligned} S_{p,\ell } = \{i \in N \mid p \in A_i \text { and } u_i(W) \leqslant \ell \} \end{aligned}$$

and check whether \(\ell < q(S_{p,\ell })\) holds. If so, the set \(S_{p,\ell }\) induces an EJR violation. This is because \(\bigcap _{i \in S_{p,\ell }}A_i \ne \emptyset \) and \( u_i(W) \leqslant \ell < q(S_{p},\ell )\) holds for all \(i \in S_{p,\ell }\).

Now, assume that the condition is not satisfied for any party \(p \in P\) and any \(\ell \in [k]\). We claim that this proves the nonexistence of an EJR violation. Assume for contradiction that there exists a group \(S \subseteq N\) inducing an EJR violation. Let \(p \in \bigcap _{i \in S} A_i\) and \(\ell = \max _{i \in S} u_i(W)\). By definition, \(S \subseteq S_{p,\ell }\) and hence \(q(S_{p,\ell })\geqslant q(S)>\ell \), a contradiction. A straightforward implementation of this algorithm has polynomial running time \({\mathcal {O}}( |P| \, k \, n)\). \(\square \)

We observe a similar effect for proportional justified representation (PJR), a proportionality axiom introduced by [51] which is weaker than EJR. While checking whether a committee satisfies PJR is coNP-complete in the candidate-approval setting, we can solve the problem in polynomial time via submodular minimization in our setting. For a formal definition and the proof, see Appendix A.3.

6 Discussion

In this paper, we have initiated the axiomatic analysis of approval-based apportionment. On a technical level, it would be interesting to see whether the party-approval domain allows us to satisfy other combinations of axioms that are not known to be attainable in candidate-approval elections. For instance, the compatibility between strong representation axioms and certain notions of support monotonicity is an open problem [49].

We have presented our setting guided by the application of apportioning parliamentary seats to political parties. But our formal setting has other interesting applications. An example would be participatory budgeting settings where items all have equal costs and come in different types. For instance, a university department could decide how to allocate Ph.D. scholarships across different research projects, in a way that respects the preferences of funding organizations.

As another example, the literature on multiwinner elections suggests many applications to recommendation problems [54]. For instance, one might want to display a limited number of news articles, movies, or advertisements in a way that fairly represents the preferences of the audience. These preferences might be expressed not over individual pieces of content, but over content producers (such as newspapers, studios, or advertising companies), in which case our setting provides rules that decide how many items should be contributed by each source. Expressing preferences on the level of content producers is natural in repeated settings, where the relevant pieces of content change too frequently to elicit voter preferences on each occasion. Besides, content producers might reserve the right to choose which of their content should be displayed.

In the general candidate-approval setting, the search continues for rules that satisfy EJR and committee monotonicity, or core stability. But for the applications mentioned above, these guarantees are already achievable today.