Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 228))

Abstract

Mendel’s 1866 treatise “Experiments on Plant Hybrids” became the driving force of the modern science of genetics. It is suggested that Mendel’s motivation as well as his methodology were guided by his conviction that Nature’s design is “writ in the language of mathematics”, and that these were sustained by his training in physics. Although there is no way of proving this directly, evidence of Mendel’s predilection for algebraic maneuvers is drawn from Mendel’s paper and from his correspondence with Nägeli.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. I wish to thank Ruma Falk for guiding me through an understanding of the geometrical mean, and to Hans-Jörg Rheinberger for his helpful critical comments.

    Google Scholar 

  2. A facsimile of Gregor Mendel’s paper Versuche über Pflanzen-Hybriden (Brünn: Georg Gastl, 1866) is included in the catalogue of the Ausstellung 1984: Johann Gregor Mendel (1822–1884) in Salzburg, G. Czihak, Akademiestrasse, ed., 15 — A 5020 Salzburg, Austria. The English translation used here is that of Curt Stern, and Eva R. Sherwood, The Origin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book (San Francisco: Freeman, 1966), pp. 1–48.

    Google Scholar 

  3. For recent analyses of de Vries’ adoption of Mendel’s paper see: Erik Zevenhuizen, “The hereditary statistics of Hugo de Vries”, Acta Botanica Neerlandica, 47(4) (1998), pp. 427–463; Ida H. Stamhuis, Onno G. Meijer and Erik J.A. Zevenhuizen, “Hugo de Vries on heredity, 1889–1903: Statistics, Mendelian laws, pangenes, mutations”, Isis, 90 (4) (1999), pp. 238–267.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Raphael Falk, “The struggle of genetics for independence”, Journal of the History of Biology, 28 (2) (1995), pp. 219–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Stern and Sherwood, The Origin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book (cit. n. 2),p. V.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Kenneth Schaffner, “Reduction in biology: Prospects and problems”, in Proceedings of the 1974 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, R.S. Cohen, et al., ed., Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1976), pp. 613–632. For a detailed discussion see Sahotra Sarkar, Genetics and Reductionism ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998 ).

    Google Scholar 

  7. For an analytic review of the different interpretations of Mendel’s motivation see Jan Sapp, “The nine lives of Gregor Mendel”, in Experimental Inquiries, H. E. Le Grand, ed. ( Amsterdam: Kluwer, 1990 ), pp. 137–166.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ronald A. Fisher, “Has Mendel’s work been rediscovered?”Annals of Science, 1 (1936), pp. 115–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Jan Sapp, Where the Truth Lies: Franz Moewus and the Origins of Molecular Biology ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990 ), pp. 104–119.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Floyd V. Monaghan and Alain F. Corcos, “The real objective of Mendel’s paper”, Biology and Philosophy, 5(3) (1990), pp. 267–292, and the response of Raphael Falk and Sahotra Sarkar, “The real objective of Mendel’s paper”, Biology and Philosophy, 6 (4) (1991), pp. 447–451.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Leslie C. Dunn, “Mendel, his work and his place in history”, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 109(4) (1965, August 18), pp. 189–198, p. 194. See also Robert Root-Bernstein, “Mendel and methodology”, History of Science 21 (1983), pp. 275–295, and Robin Dunbar, “Mendel’s peas and fuzzy logic”, New Scientist, 38 ( 1984, August 30 ).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Dunn, “Mendel, his work and his place in history” (cit. n. 11), p. 195.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Jan Sapp, “The nine lives of Gregor Mendel” (cit. n. 7), p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Fisher, “Has Mendel’s work been rediscovered?” (cit. n. 8), p. 123.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See Gerald Holton, Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press) pp. 31–74. See also p. 453. A central thematic proposition of Kepler is that the physically real world is the world of mathematically expressed harmonies which man can discover in the chaos of events, (p. 62). I am grateful to Ute Deichmann who called my attention to Holton’s important work.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Viterslav Orel, Gregor Mendel: The First Geneticist ( Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996 ), pp. 49–51.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See, e.g. Timothy Lenoir, The Strategy of Life ( Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1989 ).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ron Amundson, “Typology reconsidered: Two doctrines on the history of evolutionary biology”, Biology and Philosophy, 13 (2) (1998), pp. 153–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. See especially Viterslav Orel, Mendel (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), but also Floyd V. Monaghan and Alain F. Corcos, “The real objective of Mendel’s paper” (cit. n. 10).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Conway Zirkle, “Gregor Mendel and his precursors”, Isis, 42 (128, part 2) (1951), pp. 97–104.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Dzierzon was accommodated in the monastery in Brno in 1865 and most probably came in contact with Mendel (V. Orel, personal communication).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Orel, Gregor Mendel: The First Geneticist. (cit. n. 16), pp. 227–230. See also Zirkle, “Gregor Mendel and his precursors” (cit. n. 20). See also Frederick B. Churchill, “August Weismann and Ferdinand Dicke]: Testing the Dzierson System”, this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Zirkle, “Gregor Mendel and his precursors” (cit. n. 20), pp. 103 and 100.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Sapp, “The nine lives of Gregor Mendel” (cit. n. 7), p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Mendel, Versuche über Pflanzen-Hybriden (cit. n. 2).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Sapp, “The nine lives of Gregor Mendel” (cit. n. 7), pp. 144–145 and 149.

    Google Scholar 

  27. This is, of course, in addition to the very important source of information on Mendel’s views and state of mind derived from Mendel’s comments and remarks in his handwriting on different works that he read — see especially Orel, Gregor Mendel: The First Geneticist (cit. n. 16).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Alain F. Corcos, and Floyd V. Monaghan, Gregor Mendel’s Experiments on Plant Hybrids: A Guided Study (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1993), p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Carl Correns, “Gregor Mendels Briefe an Carl Nägeli, 1866–1873”, Abhandlungen der Königlich Sächsichen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften, Math.-phys. Kl.,29(3) (1906), pp. 189–265, p. 206. For the English translation see: The Birth of Genetics,Supplement to Genetics,35 (5, part 2) (1950), pp. 1–47, p. 8; Stern, and Sherwood, The Origin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book (cit. n. 2), p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Correns, “Gregor Mendels Briefe an Carl Nägeli, 1866–1873”, p. 214; The Birth of Genetics,p. 11–12; Stern, and Sherwood, The Origin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book,p. 73 (all cit. n. 29). Mendel’s term Mittelzahl was translated as `mean’, while mittlere Proportinale zu den beiden anderen,i.e. `the central/middle proportion of the other two’, was translated as `geometric mean’.

    Google Scholar 

  31. See Correns, “Gregor Mendels Briefe an Carl Nägeli, 1866–1873” (cit. n. 29) footnote 2, p. 211.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Correns, “Gregor Mendels Briefe an Carl Nägeli, 1866–1873”, p. 233; The Birth of Genetics,p. 22; Stern, and Sherwood, The Origin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book,p. 90 (all cited n. 29).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Correns, “Gregor Mendels Briefe an Carl Nägeli, 1866–1873” (cit. n. 29), footnote 1, p. 214: “Es scheint mir hier nur ein zufälliges übereinstimmen vorzuliegen.”

    Google Scholar 

  34. This distinction between genotype and phenotype was only introduced in 1909 by W. Johannsen, Elemente der exakten Erblichkeitslehre ( Jena: Gustav Fischer, 1909 ).

    Google Scholar 

  35. See Ruma Falk, Understanding Probability and Statistics: A Book of Problems, (Wellesley, MA: A.K. Peters, 1993), “Which Mean Do You Mean?” pp. 137–138; see also G. Udny Yule and M.G. Kendall, An Introduction to the Theory of Statistics, Fourteenth edition ( London: Charles Griffin and Company, 1950 ), pp. 118–120.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See Robert Olby, Origins of Mendelism (Chicago and London: Chicago University Press, 2nd edition, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Zevenhuizen, “The hereditary statistics of Hugo de Vries”; Stamhuis, Meijer and Zevenhuizen, “Hugo de Vries on heredity, 1889–1903” (all cit, n. 3).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Dominance was “raised” to the status of an essential law, rather than an empirical observation, in 1900 by Hugo de Vries in his “rediscovery” papers. See Falk, “The struggle of genetics for independence” (cit. n. 4).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Stern and Sherwood, The Origin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book (cit. n. 2), pp. 22–23.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Falk, R. (2001). Mendel’s Hypothesis. In: Allen, G.E., MacLeod, R.M. (eds) Science, History and Social Activism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 228. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2956-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2956-7_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5968-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2956-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics