Skip to main content

Contingency and Inherency in Evolutionary Developmental Biology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
EPSA Philosophical Issues in the Sciences
  • 542 Accesses

Abstract

The morphological organization of organisms is predictable to a certain degree from the material properties and generative rules of their constituent tissues and cells. This adds a principle to (‘externalist’) natural selection, which Müller and Newman have dubbed “inherency.” Something is inherent if it will always happen (e.g., entropy) or if the potentiality for it always exists, even if its actuality can be obstructed. In evolution, inherency means that the morphological motifs of modern-day organisms have their origins in generic forms assumed by cell masses interacting with one another and their microenvironments, and were only later integrated into developmental repertoires by stabilizing and canalizing genetic evolution. Thus, the causal basis of phenotypic evolution is not reduced to gene regulatory evolution and population genetic events, but includes the formative factors inherent to the evolving organisms themselves, such as their physical material properties, their self-organizing capacities, and their reactive potential to external influence. Regarding development, inherency locates the causal basis of morphogenesis in the dynamics of interaction between genes, cells, and tissues, each of which are endowed with their own ‘autonomous’ physical and functional properties, thus defying ‘blueprint’ or ‘program’ notions. The paper explores how inherency relates to the widely alleged ‘contingency’ of evolution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The term ‘paradigm’ is used here loosely as in common scientific parlance, and should not be taken to refer specifically to Thomas Kuhn’s theory (although many biologists use it in this way). In fact, rather than as a paradigm, the evolutionary synthesis may be more aptly characterized as a “treaty” that has allowed evolutionists and molecular biologists to work together under common presuppositions (Burian 1988; Callebaut 2010).

  2. 2.

    According to the currently dominant adaptationist perspective, phenotypic variability, although a necessary condition of any evolutionary change, is not viewed as the cause of a particular adaptive shift; rather, it is treated as a (tacit) background assumption (Sterelny 2000, p. S373).

  3. 3.

    Historical contingency is not to be confounded with contingency as understood in modal logic, where something is contingent if it is neither necessary nor impossible (which is not identical to “possible,” since what is necessary must also be possible).

  4. 4.

    My aim in this paper is not to articulate, let alone to defend, my personal stance on this issue (Elgin 2006 is a good discussion of the state of the art). Let me just say here that I sympathize with Van Fraassen’s (1989) constructive empiricist position that there are no unproblematic criteria for laws of nature, and that we’d better dispense with the notion of laws at all in the philosophy of science. Giere (1999) offers additional arguments to the effect that we can understand the workings of science (his focus is on physics) without invoking laws of nature from a constructive realist perspective.

  5. 5.

    This is in reference to the naïve correspondence view of fitness propounded by Konrad Lorenz, according to which “the hoof of the horse is already adapted to the ground of the steppe before the horse is born” (Lorenz [1962] 1982, pp. 124–125). More generally, Lewontin (1982, p. 162) rejects the “problem-solution model” according to which evolution is to be regarded as the “solution” by species of some predetermined “problems” on the grounds that “it is the life activities of the species themselves that determine both the problems and solutions simultaneously.”

  6. 6.

    Lewontin’s (1982) article is justly regarded as pioneering the current view of niche construction (Odling-Smee et al. 2003).

  7. 7.

    Oyama (2000, Ch. 6, “The accidental chordate: Contingency in developmental systems”) additionally argues for a notion of development “in which contingency is central and constitutive, not merely secondary alteration of more fundamental, ‘preprogrammed’ forms” (p. 116), thus departing from the common view that development is reoccurring regularly in nature and hence (to some extent) predictable, if not programmed, while evolution is taken to be neither (Sterelny 2000, pp. S369–S370). Oyama’s postmodern celebration of developmental contingency differs from Müller and Newman’s variety of EvoDevo in that the latter, and EvoDevo in general, extend the (non-deterministic!) programming of development by including epigenetic and environmental factors.

References

  • Beatty J (1995) The evolutionary contingency thesis. In: Wolters G, Lennox JG (eds) Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences, Universitätsverlag Konstanz, Konstanz; Pittsburgh University Press, Pittsburgh, pp 45–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (2006) The principle of drift: Biology’s first law. J Philos 102:319–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM (1988) Challenges to the evolutionary synthesis. In: Hecht MK, Wallace B (eds) Evolutionary biology, vol 23. Plenum, New York, pp 247–269

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2010) The dialectics of dis/unity in the Evolutionary Synthesis and its extensions. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Toward an extended synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 443–481

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W, Rasskin-Gutman D (eds) (2005) Modularity: Understanding the development and evolution of natural complex systems. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W, Müller GB, Newman SA (2007) The organismic systems approach: Streamlining the naturalistic agenda. In: Sansom R, Brandon RN (eds) Integrating evolution and development: From theory to practice. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 25–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Conway Morris S (1997) Molecular clocks: Defusing the Cambrian ‘explosion’? Curr Biol 7: R71–R74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin M (2006) There may be strict empirical laws in biology, after all. Biol Philos 21:119–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forgacs G, Newman SA (2005) Biological physics of the developing embryo. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (1986) Evolutionary biology, 2nd edn. Sinauer, Sunderland, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (1999). Science without laws. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1989) Wonderful life: the Burgess shale and the nature of history. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E (2006) Genes as followers in evolution – a post-synthesis synthesis. (Review of West-Eberhard 2003.) Biol Philos 21:143–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J, Ross D (2007) Everything must go: metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1982) Organism and environment. In: Plotkin HC (ed) Learning, development, and culture. Wiley, Chichester, pp 151–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz K (1982) Kant’s doctrine of the a priori in the light of contemporary biology. In: Plotkin HC (ed) Learning, development, and culture. Wiley, Chichester, pp 121–143. Originally published in General Systems 7:23–35 (1962)

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2007) Evo-devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nat Rev Genet 8:943–949

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB, Newman SA (2003) Origination of organismal form: The forgotten cause in evolutionary theory. In: Müller GB, Newman SA (eds) Origination of organismal form: beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 3–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA (1994) Generic physical mechanisms of tissue morphogenesis: a common basis for development and evolution. J Evol Biol 7:467–488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, SA (2005) The pre-Mendelian, pre-Darwinian world: shifting relations between genetic and epigenetic mechanisms in early multicellular evolution. J Biosci 30:75–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA, Müller GB (2006) Genes and form: Inherency in the evolution of developmental mechanisms. In: Neumann-Held EM, Rehmann-Sutter C (eds) Genes in development: rereading the molecular paradigm. Duke University Press, Durham, NC, pp 38–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA, Forgacs G, Müller GB (2006) Before programs: the physical origination of multicellular forms. Int J Dev Biol 50:289–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee J, Laland KL, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (2000) Evolution’s eye: a systems view of the biology-culture divide. Duke University Press, Durham, NC

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2000) Philosophy of biology, 2nd edn. Westview Press, Boulder, CO

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2003) Contingency or inevitability? What would happen if the evolutionary tape were replayed? New York Times, November 30

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2000) Development, evolution, and adaptation. Philos Sci 67:S369–S387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen BC (1989) Laws and symmetry. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams GC (1985) A defense of reductionism in evolutionary biology. Oxford Surveys Evol Biol 2:1–27

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Werner Callebaut .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Callebaut, W. (2010). Contingency and Inherency in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. In: Suárez, M., Dorato, M., Rédei, M. (eds) EPSA Philosophical Issues in the Sciences. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3252-2_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics