Skip to main content

A Geometric Approach to Temptation

  • Chapter
  • 2769 Accesses

Abstract

We provide a simple geometric proof of the Gul and Pesendorfer’s (Econometrica 69(6):1403–1435, 2001) utility representation theorem about choice under temptation without self-control. We extract two incomplete orders from preferences: temptation relation and resistance relation. We characterize those relations geometrically and obtain temptation utility using a separation method à la Aumann (Econometrica 30(3):445–462, 1962).

The original article first appeared in the Journal of Mathematical Economics 48:92–97, 2012. A newly written addendum has been added to this book chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As in the literature of non-expected utility theories, identifying the nature of violations of a particular model (expected utility model in the literature) is an important issue in order to develop a new model that accommodates the violations. See for example MacCrimmon and Larsson (1979) and Machina (1983). In the literature of temptation, Noor and Takeoka (2010) extend the Gul–Pesendorfer’s self-control model to admit an individual’s ability to exert self-control to depend on the faced menu. Providing a minimal generalization to the Gul–Pesendorfer model, they retain linearity of temptation utility. To this end, they characterize linear temptation utility in a way similar to ours.

  2. 2.

    We borrow the term “Strotz model” from Gul and Pesendorfer (2005).

  3. 3.

    See Kreps (1988).

  4. 4.

    See (1979) and Gul and Pesendorfer (2005) for another interpretation of Axiom 4. Those authors provide a behavioral foundation for Strotz’s model of changing tastes (Strotz 1955) in the environment with menus of deterministic options.

  5. 5.

    The fact that these orders are strict partial orders is proved in Lemma 2 below.

  6. 6.

    No Self-Control implies T = T and R = R . But, these equalities do not necessarily hold under Set Betweenness.

  7. 7.

    Recently, Kopylov (2009a) proved the self-control representation theorem for a more general choice object than the one considered here and applied it to characterize various models associated with temptation. His proof is not geometric but rather constructive and shorter than existing proofs.

  8. 8.

    It is straightforward to verify that the regularity defined here is equivalent to that of Gul and Pesendorfer (2001). It is also straightforward to prove the Strotz representation theorem in the non-regular case. Set v: = u for the case that \(\{x\} \succ \{ y\}\) implies \(\{x\} \sim \{ x,y\}\) and \(v:= -u\) for the case that \(\{x\} \succ \{ y\}\) implies \(\{x,y\} \sim \{ y\}\). We can then easily prove that U is the Strotz model with u and v.

  9. 9.

    Recently, an independent work, Noor and Takeoka (2010), adopts a similar method to ours for characterizing of temptation utility and prove the menu-dependent self-control representation theorem.

  10. 10.

    This means that { − u, v} is an expected multi-utility representation of T in the sense of Shapley and Baucells (1998) and Dubra et al. (2004).

  11. 11.

    To be precise, they say that x is more tempting than y when \(\{x\} \sim \{ x,y\}\) in the case of \(\{x\}\not\sim \{y\}\) and when \(\{y\} \sim \{ y,z\}\) implies \(\{x\} \sim \{ x,z\}\) in the case of \(\{x\} \sim \{ y\}\).

  12. 12.

    To be more exact, the identification problem causes discontinuity of P as in the counterexample. Hence, its expected utility representation does not exist in general. Note that the finite alternatives setting as in Kreps (1979) and Gul and Pesendorfer (2005) is free from this gap. It is because only important thing in the finite setting is that the relation has a utility representation, not expected utility representation.

  13. 13.

    Gul and Pesendorfer (2001) proves the theorem by directly constructing a temptation utility. This constructive approach and the geometric approach taken here bring us additional but different benefits beyond just establishing the representation theorem. The former directly tells us how to calibrate temptation, whereas the latter directly defines temptation and self-control in terms of preferences, so that it directly relates temptation and self-control utilities to the particular intuitive properties of the underlying preferences.

  14. 14.

    As Gul and Pesendorfer (2001, footnote 6) conjecture, there is another approach to prove the theorem that is based on a representation theorem characterizing a general model called a finite additive expected utility representation. See Dekel et al. (2009) for the case of finite Z and Kopylov (2009b) for a more general choice object.

  15. 15.

    Let \(\succapprox\) be a binary relation over \(\mathcal{A}\). Say that \(\succapprox\) is continuous if the sets \(\{B \in \mathcal{A}\vert B \succapprox A\}\) and \(\{B \in \mathcal{A}\vert A \succapprox B\}\) are closed.

    Axiom  2 (Continuity)

    \(\succapprox\) is continuous.

    Unlike the Strotz models, the costly self-control models are continuous in menu. Hence, compared with the Strorz representation theorem, Axiom 2 is strengthened to Axiom  :ref ch21:axi2 in the costly self-control representation theorem.

  16. 16.

    Similarly, we can show that U({⋅,x}) is cardinally equivalent to w over set \(\big\{y \in \varDelta \ \big\vert \ w(y) \geq w(x)\ \text{and}\ v(x) \geq v(y)\big\}\).

  17. 17.

    Similarly, the ranking of {x, y} and {x, z} is determined by the self-control ranking of y and z when x is more tempting than both y and z but when the individual can resist the temptation.

References

  • Abe K (2011) A geometric approach to temptation and self-control. Mimeograph, Osaka University

    Google Scholar 

  • Abe K (2012) A geometric approach to temptation. J Math Econ 48(2):92–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aliprantis CD, Border KC (2006) Infinite dimensional analysis, 3rd edn. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann RJ (1962) Utility theory without the completeness axiom. Econometrica 30(3):445–462

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel E, Lipman BL, Rustichini A (2009) Temptation-driven preferences. Rev Econ Stud 76(3):937–971

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubra J, Maccheroni F, Ok EA (2004) Expected utility theory without the completeness axiom. J Econ Theory 115(1):118–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1972) Alternative axiomatizations of one-way expected utility. Ann Math Stat 43(5):1648–1651

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glöckner H (2003) Positive definite functions on infinite-dimensional convex cones. Memoirs Am Math Soc 166(789):1–128

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gul F, Pesendorfer W (2001) Temptation and self-control. Econometrica 69(6):1403–1435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gul F, Pesendorfer W (2005) The revealed preference theory of changing tastes. Rev Econ Stud 72(2):429–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes RB (1975) Geometric functional analysis and its applications. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly JL, Namioka I (1976) Linear topological spaces. Springer, New York (Reprint of the 1963 edition published by Van Nostrand, Princeton)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kopylov I (2009a) Temptations in general settings. B.E. J Theor Econ (Advances) 9(1):Article 31

    Google Scholar 

  • Kopylov I (2009b) Finite additive utility representations for preferences over menus. J Econ Theory 144(1):354–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps DM (1979) On sophisticated choice of opportunity sets. Stanford GSB Research Papers No. 494, Stanford University

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreps DM (1988) Notes on the theory of choice. Westview Press, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCrimmon KR, Larsson S (1979) Utility theory: axioms versus ‘Paradoxes’. In: Allais M, Hagen Ole (eds) Expected utility hypotheses and the Allais paradox. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 333–409

    Google Scholar 

  • Machina MJ (1983) Generalized expected utility analysis and the nature of observed violations of the independence axiom,” In: Stigum BP, Wenstøp F (ed) Foundations of utility and risk theory with applications. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 263–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Noor J, Takeoka N (2010) Menu-dependent self-control. Mimeograph, Boston University and Yokohama National University

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudin W (1991) Functional analysis, 2nd edn. McGraw-Hill, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS, Baucells M (1998) A theory of multiperson utility. Working Paper No. 779, Department of Economics, UCLA

    Google Scholar 

  • Strotz RH (1955) Myopia and inconsistency in dynamic utility maximization. Rev Econ Stud 23(3):165–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to express my appreciation to Hideo Suehiro for invaluable discussions and encouragement. I would also like to thank Kazuya Hyogo, Hajime Kobayashi, Noriaki Matsushima, Eiichi Miyagawa, Wolfgang Pesendorfer, and Norio Takeoka for their valuable comments and suggestions. Very useful remarks of two anonymous reviewers and the editor have lead to an improved presentation of the results. Responsibility for any remaining errors rests with the author. The addendum part was supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant Number 24730166.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Koji Abe .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendix: Omitted Proof

Proof (Proof of Lemma 4)

Take x, y ∈ Δ with xT y arbitrarily. Let us first show that \(z - y \in \mathrm{ span}(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}})\) for any z ∈ Δ. Consider the linear subspace spanned by \(S:=\{ x - y,z - y\}\) and denote it by span(S). If these underlying vectors are linearly dependent, then \(z - y =\lambda (x - y) \in \mathrm{ span}(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}})\) for some \(\lambda \neq 0\). Assume that these vectors are linearly independent, that is, span(S) has dimension 2. Define the set \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}(y):=\{ z^{{\prime}}- y\vert z^{{\prime}}T^{{\ast}}y\}\) and let \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}_{s}(y)\) denote the intersection of \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}(y)\) and span(S). It is straightforward to verify that \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}_{s}(y)\) is a convex set. Moreover, this has dimension 2. Suppose to the contrary that \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}_{s}(y)\) has dimension 1. Then, for any α ∈ (0, 1),

$$\displaystyle{[\alpha x + (1-\alpha )z] - y =\alpha (x - y) + (1-\alpha )(z - y)\notin \mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}_{ s}(y).}$$

This means that \(\mathit{yR}^{{\ast}}[\alpha x + (1-\alpha )z]\) for all α ∈ (α , 1), where α  ∈ (0, 1) is a number such that \(\{y\} \succ \{\alpha ^{{\ast}}x + (1 -\alpha ^{{\ast}})z\}\). As we stated in the proof of Lemma 2, this contradicts Upper Semi-Continuity of \(\succapprox\). Thus, \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}_{s}(y)\) has dimension 2. We can then take an algebraically relative interior point \(z^{{\prime}}- y \in \mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}_{s}(y)\) (see p.9 in Holmes 1975). From its algebraic properties, there is a \(\lambda> 0\) such that

$$\displaystyle{[z^{{\prime}}-\lambda (z - y)] - y = z^{{\prime}}- y -\lambda (z - y) \in \mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}_{ s}(y).}$$

This means that \([z^{{\prime}}-\lambda (z - y)]T^{{\ast}}y\) for some \(\lambda> 0\). Hence,

$$\displaystyle{-\lambda (z - y) = [z^{{\prime}}-\lambda (z - y)] - y - (z^{{\prime}}- y) \in \mathrm{ span}(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}).}$$

As a result, \(z - y \in \mathrm{ span}(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}})\).

We now show that \(\varDelta -\varDelta \subsetneq \mathrm{ span}(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}})\). Take \(z,z^{{\prime}}\in \varDelta\) arbitrarily. Then, as shown above, both zy and \(z^{{\prime}}- y\) are in \(\mathrm{span}(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}})\). Therefore, \(z - z^{{\prime}} = (z - y) - (z^{{\prime}}- y) \in \mathrm{ span}(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}})\). This completes the proof.

Addendum: On the Geometry of Temptation and Self-Control

This addendum has been newly written for this book chapter.

As stated in Remark 2, Abe (2011) demonstrates the usefulness of our geometric approach to menu preferences beyond the Strotz model. By taking the geometric approach, Abe (2011) provides an alternative proof of the costly self-control representation theorem in Gul and Pesendorfer (2001).Footnote 13 ,  Footnote 14 Here, we briefly supplement Remark 2 by providing an outline of the proof provided in Abe (2011).

We begin by summarizing Gul and Pesendorfer’s costly self-control representation theorem.

Definition 2

A utility function U on menus is said to be a Gul and Pesendorfer’s costly self-control model, hereafter referred to as a costly self-control model , if it is a function of the form:

$$\displaystyle{U(A) =\max _{x\in A}\big\{u(x) + v(x)\big\} -\max _{y\in A}\big\{v(y)\big\}}$$

for some \(u,v \in \mathcal{C}\).

The costly self-control models are characterized by a behavioral regularity on menu preferences named Set Betweenness.

Axiom 4 (Set Betweenness )

\(A \succapprox B\) implies \(A \succapprox A \cup B \succapprox B\).

Set Betweenness relaxes No Self-Control and allows for the possibility that \(A \succ A \cup B \succ B\). This possibility displays the notion of temptation and costly self-control. Suppose that B contains a tempting alternative. We can view \(A \cup B \succ B\) as meaning that when facing menu \(A \cup B\), the individual uses self-control and can resist the temptation. We then interpret \(A \succ A \cup B\) as meaning that exercising self-control is costly. The main theorem in Gul and Pesendorfer (2001) is summarized as follows.Footnote 15

The Costly Self-Control Representation Theorem. \(\succapprox\) satisfies Preference, Continuity, Independence, and Set Betweenness if and only if it has a costly self-control representation , that is, there exists a costly self-control model U such that \(A \succapprox B\) if and only if U(A) ≥ U(B).

We provide the proof outline on the sufficiency of the axioms in Abe (2011). In what follows, let U be a utility representation of \(\succapprox\) derived as in Lemma 1 and u be a commitment utility derived by restricting U on singleton menus. Consider a nontrivial preference relation \(\succapprox\), that is, there are x, y ∈ Δ such that \(\{x\} \succ \{ y\}\). The proof outline is as follows. First, in a similar way as in Sect. 3, we can characterize the geometry of temptation under Set Betweenness. Specifically, Set Betweenness induces the following four strict partial orders satisfying Strong Independence.

  • A weak temptation relation T is defined by yTx if \(\{x\} \succ \{ x,y\}\).

  • A strong temptation relation T is defined by yT x if \(\{x\} \succ \{ x,y\} \sim \{ y\}\).

  • A weak resistance relation R is defined by xRy if \(\{x,y\} \succ \{ y\}\).

  • A strong resistance relation R is defined by xR y if \(\{x\} \sim \{ x,y\} \succ \{ y\}\).

Furthermore, the weak temptation relation T and the weak resistance relation R are both Strong Archimedean. Define four cones corresponding to the four relations as follows.

  • A weak temptation cone is defined by \(\mathcal{T} =\big\{\lambda (y - x)\ \vert \ \lambda> 0,\ \mathit{yTx}\big\}\).

  • A strong temptation cone is defined by \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}} =\big\{\lambda (y - x)\ \vert \ \lambda> 0,\ \mathit{yT}^{{\ast}}x\big\}\).

  • A weak resistance cone is defined by \(\mathcal{R} =\big\{\lambda (y - x)\ \vert \ \lambda> 0,\ \mathit{xRy}\big\}\).

  • A strong resistance cone is defined by \(\mathcal{R}^{{\ast}} =\big\{\lambda (y - x)\ \vert \ \lambda> 0,\ \mathit{xR}^{{\ast}}y\big\}\).

Then, the four cones \(\mathcal{T}\), \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}\), \(\mathcal{R}\), and \(\mathcal{R}^{{\ast}}\) are convex cones that represent their corresponding relations, respectively. Furthermore, the weak temptation cone \(\mathcal{T}\) and the weak resistance cone \(\mathcal{R}\) are both faceless.

Second, we derive affine numerical representations of temptation and resistance (self-control) by the separation argument, and obtain \(v,w \in \mathcal{C}\) such that for any x, y ∈ Δ with \(\{x\} \succ \{ y\}\), (i) \(\{x\} \succ \{ x,y\}\) if and only if v(y) > v(x) and (ii) \(\{x,y\} \succ \{ y\}\) if and only if w(x) > w(y). We determine temptation utility v by openly separating \(\mathcal{T}\) from \(\mathcal{R}^{{\ast}}\) and self-control utility w by openly separating \(\mathcal{R}\) from \(\mathcal{T}^{{\ast}}\). Note that if u(x) > u(y), then, by construction, v(x) ≥ v(y) implies w(x) > w(y). With this fact, we can show that self-control utility w must be written by \(w = au + bv + c\) for some constant a, b > 0 and \(c \in \mathbb{R}\). This means that the indifference curve of w lies between those of u and v when they pass a common point, and this also implies w(x) > w(y) and v(y) > v(x) if and only if \(\{x\} \succ \{ x,y\} \succ \{ y\}\).

Third, we can characterize U with w and v. The next lemma establishes this.

Lemma 7

U({x,⋅}) is cardinally equivalent to − v over set \(\big\{y \in \varDelta \ \big\vert \ w(x) \geq \mathit{w}(y)\ \text{ and }\ \mathit{v}(y) \geq v(x)\big\}\).Footnote 16

This lemma states that the ranking of {x, y} and {x, z} is determined by the temptation ranking of y and z when both y and z are more tempting than x but when the individual can resist the temptations.Footnote 17 This observation leads us to the desired form of representation. Suppose \(\{x\} \succ \{ x,y\} \succ \{ y\}\). Take a z such that w(x) = w(z) and v(y) = v(z). The facts derived in the second step imply \(\{x\} \succ \{ x,z\} \sim \{ z\}\). Combining this with the above lemma, we then find \(\{x,y\} \sim \{ x,z\} \sim \{ z\}\). Recall from the second step that an appropriate scale-normalized commitment utility is the difference between the self-control utility and the scale-normalized temptation utility: \(\mathit{au} + c = w -\mathit{bv}\). Therefore, we can calibrate the utility value of {x, y} by the difference between the self-control utility of z and the normalized temptation utility of z. By way of choosing z, we can calibrate the utility value of {x, y} by the difference between the self-control utility of x and the normalized temptation utility of y, that is, w(x) −bv(y). This means that the utility value of {x, y} is measured by Gul and Pesendorfer’s costly self-control representation form \(\hat{u}(x) +\hat{ v}(x) -\hat{ v}(y)\) if we define \(\hat{u} = \mathit{au} + c\) and \(\hat{v} = \mathit{bv}\). More formally, we can prove the next lemma in this line and hence complete the proof.

Lemma 8

Define \(\hat{U}\) and \(\hat{v}\) by \(\hat{U}:= aU + c\) and \(\hat{v}:= \mathit{bv}\) with a,b,c derived in the second step. Let \(\hat{u}\) be the restriction of \(\hat{U}\) on singleton menus. Then, \(\hat{U}\) is a representation of \(\succapprox\) and a costly self-control model.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Japan

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Abe, K. (2016). A Geometric Approach to Temptation. In: Ikeda, S., Kato, H., Ohtake, F., Tsutsui, Y. (eds) Behavioral Economics of Preferences, Choices, and Happiness. Springer, Tokyo. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-4-431-55402-8_21

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics