Skip to main content

Abstract

The capacity for thought underpins relational closeness, yet theorists swayed by human/nature dualisms tend to deny thoughts to most beings. They do so based on the assumption that minds are exclusively the product of material structures that only human-like animals have. But, with human/nature dualisms eliminated, one doesn’t need a human-like neurophysiology or even any particular physiology to have a mind. In exploring the Theory of Mind and the “mind-brain problem,” critiques of the origin of the mind in supervenience, multiple realizability, and especially emergence theories reveal materialist fault lines. For example, emergence is ultimately an undefinable term used to cover the gap between human/nature dualist suggestions that minds are qualitatively different from brains yet are materially rooted in human-like ones. When such dualist explanations are removed, and being-neutral criteria applied, it’s not only possible for plants to have minds, but to entertain the same possibility in “inanimate” beings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Adams, D. K. (1928). The inference of mind. Psychological Review, 35(3), 235–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adler, R. W. (2007). Restoring Colorado river ecosystems: A troubled sense of immensity. Washington, DC: Island Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, S. (1920). Space, time, and deity: The Gifford lectures at Glasgow, 1916–1918. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Automaton. (2018, June). Oxford English Dictionary Online. Retrieved from http://www.oed.com.

  • Backster, C. (1968). Evidence of a primary perception in plant life. International Journal of Parapsychology, 10(4), 329–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baluška, F., Mancuso, S., & Volkmann, D. (2005). Communication in plants. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. (2007). Meeting the universe halfway: Quantum physics and the entanglement of matter and meaning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (2010). A vitalist stopover on the way to a new materialism. In D. Coole & S. Frost (Eds.), New materialisms: Ontology, agency, and politics (pp. 47–69). Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berry, D. L. (2012). Mutuality: The vision of Martin Buber. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2013). Multiple realizability. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/multiple-realizability.

  • Buber, M. (1970). I and thou. (W. Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. (Original work published 1923).

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (2003). Between man and man. (R. Gregor-Smith Trans.). London: Routledge. (Original work published 1947).

    Google Scholar 

  • Callaway, R. M., Pennings, S. C., & Richards, C. L. (2003). Phenotypic plasticity and interactions among plants. Ecology, 84(5), 1115–1128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calvo Garzón, F. (2007). The quest for cognition in plant neurobiology. Plant Signaling & Behavior, 2(4), 208–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calvo Garzón, P., & Keijzer, F. (2011). Plants: Adaptive behavior, root-brains, and minimal cognition. Adaptive Behavior, 19(3), 155–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carello, C., Vaz, D., Blau, J. J., & Petrusz, S. (2012). Unnerving intelligence. Ecological Psychology, 24(3), 241–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2004). On being simple minded. American Philosophical Quarterly, 41(3), 205–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casacuberta, D., Ayala, S., & Vallverdú, J. (2010). Embodying cognition: A morphological perspective. In J. Vallverdú (Ed.), Thinking machines and the philosophy of computer science: Concepts and principles (pp. 344–366). Hershey, PA: Information Science Reference.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chapin, F. S., Walker, L. R., Fastie, C. L., & Sharman, L. C. (1994). Mechanisms of primary succession following deglaciation at Glacier Bay, Alaska. Ecological Monographs, 64(2), 149–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, B. J., During, H. J., & Anten, N. P. (2012). Detect thy neighbor: Identity recognition at the root level in plants. Plant Science, 195, 157–167.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, N. L., & Feeney, B. C. (2000). A safe haven: An attachment theory perspective on support seeking and caregiving in intimate relationships. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78(6), 1053–1073.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Cruse, H., & Wehner, R. (2011). No need for a cognitive map: Decentralized memory for insect navigation. PLoS Computational Biology, 7(3), e1002009.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Cudworth, E., & Hobden, S. (2015). Liberation for Straw Dogs? Old materialism, new materialism, and the challenge of an emancipatory posthumanism. Globalizations, 12(1), 134–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, S. (2000). What is a mind?: An integrative introduction to the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D. R. (1981). The question of animal awareness: Evolutionary continuity of mental experience. New York: Rockefeller University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D. R. (2013). Animal minds: Beyond cognition to consciousness. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruntman, M., & Novoplansky, A. (2004). Physiologically mediated self/non-self discrimination in roots. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 101(11), 3863–3867.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, W. (2001). The emergent self. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (1983). A feeling for the organism, 10th anniversary edition: The life and work of Barbara McClintock. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kessler, N. (2012). Chaos or Relationalism? A Pragmatist Metaphysical Foundation for Human-Nature Relationships. The Trumpeter, 28(1), 43–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1997). The mind-body problem: Taking stock after forty years. Noûs, 31(s11), 185–207.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2000). Mind in a physical world: An essay on the mind-body problem and mental causation. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Likens, G. E., Bormann, F. H., Johnson, N. M., Fisher, D., & Pierce, R. S. (1970). Effects of forest cutting and herbicide treatment on nutrient budgets in the Hubbard Brook watershed-ecosystem. Ecological Monographs, 40(1), 23–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lisci, M., Monte, M., & Pacini, E. (2003). Lichens and higher plants on stone: A review. International Biodeterioration & Biodegradation, 51(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marder, M. (2012). Plant intentionality and the phenomenological framework of plant intelligence. Plant Signaling & Behavior, 7(11), 1365–1372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (2005). Can we solve the mind-body problem? In T. O'Connor & D. Robb (Eds.), Philosophy of mind: Contemporary readings (pp. 438–457). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, A. H. (1997). Are plants conscious? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(3), 215–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, N. (1984). Caring: A feminine approach to ethics & moral education. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nollman, J. (1987). Animal dreaming: (The art and science of interspecies communication). New York: Bantam.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. (1994). Emergent properties. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31(2), 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective neuroscience: The foundations of human and animal emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1960). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, & A. W. Burks, Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1977). Part I. In K. R. Popper & J. C. Eccles (Eds.), The self and its brain (pp. 3–224). Berlin: Springer International.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Robb, D., & Heil, J. (2013). Mental causation. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-causation.

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sanders, C. R. (2003). Actions speak louder than words: Close relationships between humans and nonhuman animals. Symbolic Interaction, 26(3), 405–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scientific Method. (2018, June). Oxford English Dictionary Online. Retrieved from http://www.oed.com.

  • Sperry, R. W. (1969). A modified concept of consciousness. Psychological Review, 76(6), 532–536.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Sperry, R. W. (1980). Mind-brain interaction: Mentalism, yes; dualism, no. Neuroscience, 5(2), 195–206.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Sperry, R. W. (1987). Structure and significance of the consciousness revolution. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 8(1), 37–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, L. (1971). The lives of a cell: Notes of a biology watcher. New York: Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trewavas, A. (1999). Le calcium, C’est la vie: Calcium makes waves. Plant Physiology, 120(1), 1–6.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Trewavas, A. (2002). Plant intelligence: Mindless mastery. Nature, 415(6874), 841–841.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Trewavas, A. (2003). Aspects of plant intelligence. Annals of Botany, 92(1), 1–20.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Trewavas, A. (2005). Plant intelligence. Naturwissenschaften, 92(9), 401–413.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Uttal, W. R. (2005). Neural theories of mind: Why the mind-brain problem may never be solved. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kessler, N.H. (2019). Thoughts. In: Ontology and Closeness in Human-Nature Relationships. AESS Interdisciplinary Environmental Studies and Sciences Series. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-99274-7_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics