Skip to main content

Darwinism After the Modern Synthesis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

The Modern Synthesis in evolutionary biology took place in two major phases from the 1920s through the 1940s. It achieved a reconciliation between the original Darwinism and the newly discovered Mendelism, which gave birth to the field of population genetics, the mathematical core of evolutionary theory. Since that time, the field has further evolved, encompassing entirely new areas of inquiry, leading to new empirical findings, and developing new conceptual tools. In the 1960s, for instance, the invention of gel electrophoresis made it possible for the first time to directly estimate gene frequencies in natural populations. While developmental biology was initially still excluded from the synthesis, in the 1980s new techniques led to the emergence of the field of evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo). The parallel molecular revolution unfolded initially independently of evolutionary studies, until the turn of the twenty-first century, when genomics became “comparative” in nature and began importing techniques from phylogenetic analysis. The reevaluation of phenomena like phenotypic plasticity and epigenetic inheritance led to a rebirth of interest in the complexities of the genotype–phenotype map, triggering the formulation of concepts like robustness, modularity, and evolvability. Paleontology came roaring back with the theory of punctuated equilibria in the 1970s and 1980s. These many strands brought about the need for a further expansion of evolutionary theory, catalyzing discussions concerning a possible Extended Synthesis. “Darwinism” has never been more alive and pregnant with opportunities for both theoretical advancements and philosophical reflection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Loison and Herring (2017) about the surprising persistence of neo-Lamarckian ideas in France.

  2. 2.

    For those interested in a closer look, a new website has been launched to track the development of research and to foster outreach activities concerning the EES (http://extendedevolutionarysynthesis.com/).

  3. 3.

    Their paper is focused on four specific areas: evo-devo, developmental plasticity, what they call inclusive inheritance, and niche construction.

References

  • Alberch P (1991) From genes to phenotypes: dynamical systems and evolvability. Genetics 84:5–11

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Alcock J (2017) The behavioral sciences and sociobiology: a Darwinian approach. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 37–60

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler PJ (1983) The eclipse of Darwinism: anti-Darwinian evolution theories in the decades around 1900. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler PJ (2003) Evolution: the history of an idea. University of California Press, Oakland

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler PJ (2017) Alternatives to Darwinism in the early twentieth century. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 195–218

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Caetano-Anollés G (ed) (2010) Evolutionary genomics and systems biology. Wiley-Blackwell, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulter JM (1915) A suggested explanation of orthogenesis in plants. Science 42:859–863

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) The origin of species by means of natural selection; or the preservation of favoured Racesn in the struggle for life. http://tinyurl.com/oyadykh. Accessed 26 Oct 2016

  • Delisle RG (2017) From Charles Darwin to the evolutionary synthesis: weak and diffused connections only. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 133–168

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Depew DJ (2017) Darwinism in the 20th century: productive encounters with saltation, acquired characteristics, and development. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 61–88

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Depew DJ, Weber BH (2011) The fate of Darwinism: evolution after the modern synthesis. Biol Theor 6:89–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1937) Genetics and the origin of species. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1973) Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. Am Biol Teach 35:125–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge N, Gould SJ (1972) Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism. In: Schopf TJM (ed) Models in paleobiology. Freeman Cooper, San Francisco, pp 82–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito M (2017) The organismal synthesis: holistic science and developmental evolution in the english-speaking world, 1915–1954. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 219–242

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetically theory of natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gavrilets S (1999) A dynamical theory of speciation on holey adaptive landscapes. Am Nat 154:1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt R (1940) The material basis of evolution. Yale University Press, Yale

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1985) Ontogeny and phylogeny. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (2002) The structure of evolutionary theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ, Eldredge N (1977) Punctuated equilibria: the tempo and mode of evolution reconsidered. Paleobiology 3:115–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haeckel EHP (1866) Generelle Morphologie der Organismen. Allgemeine Grundzüge der Organischen Formen-wissenschaft, Mechanisch Begründet Durch die von Charles Darwin Reformirte Descendenztheorie. G. Reimer. https://archive.org/details/generellemorphol01haec. Accessed 4 Nov 2016

  • Haldane JBS (1932) The causes of evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoelzer GA, Smith E, Pepper JW (2006) On the logical relationship between natural selection and self-organization. J Evol Biol 19:1785–1794

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Huxley JS (1942) Evolution: the modern synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (1999) Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: the Lamarckian dimension. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2005) Evolution in four dimension: genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonski D (2000) Micro- and macroevolution: scale and hierarchy in evolutionary biology and paleobiology. Paleobiology 26:15–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonski D (2005) Evolutionary innovations in the fossil record: the intersection of ecology, development, and macroevolution. J Exp Zool 304B:504–519

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonski D (2008) Species selection: theory and data. Annu Rev Ecol Evol Syst 39:501–524

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonski D, Shubin NH (2015) The future of the fossil record: paleontology in the 21st century. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 112:4852–4858

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan DS (1920) Orthogenesis among fishes. Science 52:13–14

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan JM (2006) More misuses of evolutionary psychology. Metascience 15:177–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimura M (1983) The neutral theory of molecular evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner MW, Gerhart JC (2005) The plausibility of life: resolving Darwin’s Dilemma. Yale University Press, Yale

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera U (2017) Symbiogenesis and cell evolution: an anti-Darwinian research agenda? In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 302–332

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Sterelny K (2006) Seven reasons (not) to neglect niche construction. Evolution 60:1751–1762

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Uller T, Feldman M, Sterelny K, Muller GB et al (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Nature 514:161–164. http://tinyurl.com/myohvp2. Accessed 26 Oct 2016

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Uller T, Feldman M, Sterelny K, Muller GB et al (2015) The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions, and predictions. Proc R Soc B 282. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2015.1019

  • Levit GS, Hossfeld U (2017) Major research traditions in 20th century evolutionary biology: the relations of Germany’s Darwinism with them. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 169–194

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis EB (1978) A gene complex controlling segmentation in Drosophila. Nature 276:565–570

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC, Hubby JL (1966) A molecular approach to the study of genic heterozygosity in natural populations. II Amount of variation and degree of heterozygosity in natural populations of Drosophila pseudoobscura. Genetics 54:595–609

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Lipman CB (1922) Orthogenesis in bacteria. Am Nat 56:105–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loison L, Herring E (2017) Lamarckian research programs in French biology (1900–1970). In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 243–270

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Love A (2006) Evolutionary morphology and evo-devo: hierarchy and novelty. Theor Biosci 124:317–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (2007) The origins of genome architecture. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1942) Systematics and the origin of species. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2007) Evo-devo: extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nat Rev Genet 8:943–949

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA, Gabor F, Muller GB (2006) Before programs: the physical origination of multicellular forms. Int J Dev Biol 50:289–299

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Otha T (2002) Near-neutrality in evolution of genes and gene regulation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 99:16134–16137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2001) Phenotypic plasticity: beyond nature and nurture. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2007) Do we need an extended evolutionary synthesis? Evolution 61:2743–2749

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2008a) What, if anything, is an evolutionary novelty? Philos Sci 75:887–898

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2008b) Is evolvability evolvable? Nat Rev Genet 9:75–82

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2016) Progress in science. Plato’s Footnote. http://tinyurl.com/PlatoFootnote1, http://tinyurl.com/PlatoFootnote2, http://tinyurl.com/PlatoFootnote3. Accessed 26 Oct 2016

  • Pigliucci M, Muller GB (eds) (2010) Evolution – the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Prud’homme B, Gompel N, Carroll SB (2007) Emerging principles of regulatory evolution. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104:8605–8612

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Real LA, Brown JH (1991) Foundations of ecology. Classic papers with commentaries. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rollo CD (1995) Phenotypes: their epigenetics, ecology and evolution. Chapman & Hall, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlichting CD, Pigliucci M (1998) Phenotype evolution, a reaction norm perspective. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanahan T (2017) Selfish genes and lucky breaks: Richard Dawkins’ and Stephen Jay Gould’s: divergent Darwinian agendas. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 11–36

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson GG (1944) Tempo and mode in evolution. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stebbins GL (1950) Variation and evolution in plants. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiselius A (1937) A new apparatus for electrophoretic analysis of colloidal mixtures. Trans Faraday Soc 33:524–531

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Turner DD (2017) Paleobiology’s uneasy relationship with the Darwinian tradition: stasis as data. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 333–352

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP, Zhang J (2011) The pleiotropic structure of the genotype-phenotype map: the evolvability of complex organisms. Nat Rev Genet 12:204–213

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Watson JD, Crick FHC (1953) Molecular structure of nucleic acids. Nature 171:737–738

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Weissman A (1893) The germ-plasm: a theory of heredity. Charles Scribner’s Sons. http://tinyurl.com/gq9m765. Accessed 26 Oct 2016

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS, Wilson EO (2008) Evolution ‘for the good of the group’. Am Sci 96:380–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2015) The structure of scientific theories. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/structure-scientific-theories/. Accessed 26 Oct 2016

  • Wright S (1931) Evolution in Mendelian populations. Genetics 16:97–159

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Massimo Pi+gliucci .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pi+gliucci, M. (2017). Darwinism After the Modern Synthesis. In: Delisle, R. (eds) The Darwinian Tradition in Context. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69123-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics