Skip to main content

Knowledge in Early Modern Philosophy

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Encyclopedia of Early Modern Philosophy and the Sciences
  • 9 Accesses

Reference Point: The Aristotelian Ideal of Knowledge

This entry offers an overview of various conceptions of knowledge and knowledge acquisition in the early modern period. The starting point of this enterprise was the Aristotelian ideal of knowledge, or as it was known in the era: scientia. Different aspects of this ideal have been criticized and refined in the period, but this ideal was the unquestionable point of reference with respect to which differing accounts of knowledge had to be situated.

According to Aristotle, scientiaconsists in a system of necessary and universal truths demonstrated via syllogisms from self-evident principles. Though demonstrativity is arguably the most enduring aspect of this ideal, but there are other aspects that are also similarly important: the relevant self-evident principles are typically about formal causes, and they provide an undisputable foundation of knowledge. Since “the proper object of unqualified scientific knowledge is something which...

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 899.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Anstey PR (2005) Experimental versus speculative natural philosophy. In: Anstey PR, Schuster JA (eds) The science of human nature in the seventeenth century. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 215–242

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anstey PR (2011) John Locke and natural philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anstey PR, Schuster JA (eds) (2005) The science of human nature in the seventeenth century. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew R (1992) Descartes and the tree of knowledge. Synthese 92(1):101–116. The Thought of Marjorie Grene (Jul., 1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew R (2016) The mathematization of nature in Descartes and the first Cartesians. In: Gorham G, Hill B, Slowik E, Waters CK (eds) The language of nature: reassessing the mathematization of natural philosophy in the seventeenth century. University of Minesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 112–133

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1950) Posterior analytics. In: Ross WD (ed) The works of Aristotle translated into English, vol 1. Oxford University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon F (1863) Preparative for a natural and experimental history. In: Spedding J, Ellis RL, Heath DD (eds) The works of Francis Bacon, vol VIII. Houghton, Mifflin & Co, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon F (1952) Advancement of learning. In: Adler MJ (ed) Great books of the western world, vol 30. Britannica Encyclopaedia, Chicago, pp 1–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon F (2000) Novum Organum. In: Jardine L, Silverthorne M (eds) The new organon. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley G (1949) A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. In: Luce AA, Jessop TE (eds) The works of George Berkeley bishop of Cloyne, vol 2. Thomas Nelson & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley G (1951) De Motu. In: Luce AA, Jessop TE (eds) The works of George Berkeley bishop of Cloyne, vol 4. Thomas Nelson & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley G (1964) Alciphron, or the minute philosopher. In: Luce AA, Jessop TE (eds) The works of George Berkeley bishop of Cloyne, vol 3. Thomas Nelson & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Biener Z, Scliesser E (eds) (2014) Newton and Empiricism. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton M (2018) Theory of knowledge: mathematical and natural science. In: Antognazza MR (ed) The Oxford handbook of Leibniz. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 137–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Brook R (2017) De Motu: Berkeley’s Philosophy of Science. In: Brook R, Belfrage B (eds) The Bloomsbury companion to Berkeley. Blumsbury Academic, London, pp 158–173

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown CR, Morris WE (2014) Starting with Hume. Continuum, London/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E (1951) The philosophy of the enlightenment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen IB (1980) The Newtonian revolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • De Pierris G (2006) Hume and Locke on scientific methodology: the Newtonian legacy. Hume Studies 32:277–330

    Google Scholar 

  • Dear P (2006) The intelligibility of nature. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Demeter T (2012) Hume’s experimental method. Br J Hist Philos 20:577–599

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R (1985) Rules for the direction of the mind. In: Cottingham J, Stoothoff R, Murdoch D (eds) The philosophical writings of Descartes, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R (1991) Letters. In: Cottingham J, Stoothoff R, Murdoch D (eds) The philosophical writings of Descartes, vol 3. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Di Bella S (2018) The complete concept of an individual substance. In: Antognazza MR (ed) The Oxford handbook of Leibniz. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 119–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Dicker G (1998) Hume’s epistemology and metaphysics: an introduction. Routledge, London/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Downing L (1995) Berkeley’s case against realism about dynamics. In: Muehlmann RG (ed) Berkeley’s metaphysics: structural, interpretive, and critical essays. The Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, pp 197–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Downing L (2005) Berkeley’s natural philosophy and philosophy of science. In: Winkler KP (ed) The Cambridge companion to Berkeley. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 230–265

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne S (2012) The main business of natural philosophy: Isaac Newton’s natural-philosophical methodology. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Flage DE (2004) Berkeley's epistemic Ontology: the principles. Can J Philos 34(1):25–60

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garber D (1992) Descartes’ metaphysical physics. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrett D (2010) Spinoza’s theory of Scientia Intuitiva. In: Sorell T, Rogers GAJ, Kraye J (eds) Scientia in early modern philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 99–115

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett A (2019) Spinoza. In: Gaukroger S (ed) Knowledge in modern philosophy. Bloomsbury Academic, London, pp 63–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger S (1989) Cartesian logic. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger S (1993) Descartes: methodology. In: Parkinson GHR (ed) The Renaissance and seventeenth-century rationalism. Routledge history of philosophy, vol IV. Routledge, London, pp 156–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger S (2006) The emergence of scientific culture: science and the shaping of modernity, 1210–1685. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger S (2010) The collapse of mechanism and the rise of sensibility: science and the shaping of modernity, 1680–1760. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger S (2019) Knowledge in modern philosophy. Bloomsbury, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1978) Hume’s species of probability. Philos Stud 33(1):21–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamou P, Pécharman M (eds) (2018) Locke and Cartesian philosophy. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Harper WL (2011) Isaac Newton’s scientific method: turning data into evidence about gravity and Cosmology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hazony Y (2014) Newtonian explanatory reduction and Hume’s system of the sciences. In: Biener Z, Schliesser E (eds) Newton and empiricism. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 138–170

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse M (1964) Francis Bacon. In: O'Connor DJ (ed) A critical history of Western philosophy. Free Press, New York, pp 142–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1967) A treatise of human nature. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1989) In: Nidditch PH (ed) Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals, 3rd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jalobeanu D (2016) Disciplining experience: Francis Bacon’s experimental series and the art of experimenting. Perspect Sci 24(3):324–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jesseph DM (1993) Berkeley’s philosophy of mathematics. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1975) An essay concerning human understanding. In: Nidditch PH (ed) The Clarendon edition of the works of John Locke: an essay concerning human understanding. Clarendon, Oxford

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P, McGuire JE (2009) Descartes’s changing mind. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marion J-L (1992) Cartesian metaphysics and the role of simple natures. In: Cottingham J (ed) The Cambridge companion to Descartes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 115–140

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McRae R (1994) The theory of knowledge. In: Jolley N (ed) The Cambridge companion to Leibniz. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 176–198

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Millican P (2012) Hume’s ‘scepticism’ about induction. In: Baily A, O’Brien D (eds) The Continuum companion to Hume. Continuum, London/New York, pp 57–103

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton I (2004) Queries to the Opticks. In: Janiak A (ed) Isaac Newton: philosophical writings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 127–140

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norton DF (1981) The myth of ‘British empiricism’. Hist Eur Ideas 1(4):331–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ott W (2019) Berkeley’s best system: an alternative approach to laws of nature. J Modern Philos 1(1):4, 1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce KL (2017) Language and the structure of Berkeley’s world. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perez-Ramos A (1988) Francis Bacon 's idea of science and the Maker's knowledge tradition. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterschmitt L (2011) How Did Berkeley Read Newton? In: Boran EA, Feingold M (eds) Reading Newton in early modern Europe. Brill, Leiden, pp 290–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (2002) The logic of scientific discovery, 2nd edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Primus K (2017) Scientia Intuitiva in the Ethics. In: Melamed Y (ed) Spinoza’s ethics: a critical guide. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 169–186

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Priselac M (2017) Locke’s science of knowledge. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos A (2003) Cartesian analysis and synthesis. Stud Hist Phil Sci, Part A 34(2):265–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rickless CS (2005) The Cartesian fallacy fallacy. Noûs 39(2):309–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers GAJ (2010) John Locke and the limits of Scientia. In: Sorell T, Rogers GAJ, Kraye J (eds) Scientia in early modern philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 129–136

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser E (2005) On the origin of modern naturalism: the significance of Berkeley’s response to a Newtonian indispensibility argument. Philosophica 76:45–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser E (2009) Hume’s attack on Newton’s philosophy. In: Snobelen SD (ed) Enlightenment and dissent, Isaac Newton in the eighteenth century, vol 25, pp 167–203

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser E (2011) Newton’s challenge to philosophy: A programmatic essay. HOPOS 1:101–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser E, Demeter T (2020) Hume’s Newtonianism and anti-Newtonianism. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hume-newton/

  • Smith K (2010) Matter matters. Metaphysics and methodology in the early modern period. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sorell T (2010) Scientia and the sciences in Descartes. In: Sorell T, Rogers GAJ, Kraye J (eds) Scientia in early modern Philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 71–82

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sorell T, Rogers GAJ, Kraye J (eds) (2010) Scientia in early modern Philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinberg D (2008) Knowledge in Spinoza’s Ethics. In: Koistinen O (ed) The Cambridge companion to Spinoza’s Ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 140–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanzo A, Anstey PR (eds) (2019) Experiment, speculation and religion in early modern philosophy. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh K (2017) Newton: from certainty to probability? Philos Sci 84:866–878

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson MD (1996) Spinoza’s theory of knowledge. In: Garrett D (ed) The Cambridge companion to Spinoza. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 89–141

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson C (2018) Philosophical and scientific empiricism and rationalism in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. In: Bodenmann S, Rey A (eds) What does it mean to be an empiricist? Empiricisms in eighteenth century sciences. Springer, Cham, pp 123–138

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson C (2019) What (Else) was behind the Newtonian rejection of ‘Hypotheses’? In: Vanzo A, Anstey PR (eds) Experiment, speculation and religion in early modern philosophy. Routledge, New York, pp 158–183

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe ChT (2010) Rethinking empiricism and materialism: the revisionist view. Annales Philosophici, Philosophy Department, University of Oradea, vol 1, pp 101–113

    Google Scholar 

  • Zemplén G, Demeter T (2010) Being charitable to scientific controversies: on the demonstrativity of Newton’s experimentum crucis. Monist 93:640–656

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Krisztián Pete .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Pete, K. (2022). Knowledge in Early Modern Philosophy. In: Jalobeanu, D., Wolfe, C.T. (eds) Encyclopedia of Early Modern Philosophy and the Sciences. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-31069-5_606

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics