Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library A: ((TDLA,volume 54))

  • 215 Accesses

Abstract

One sometimes sees it suggested that the phenomenon of dilation is a problem for sets of probabilities, since your belief state becomes “less informed” on learning new evidence, and that is something that should not happen. This article explores several ways to make precise the idea of “informativeness” for a set of probabilities, and finds that this criticism of imprecise probability does not stand up to scrutiny.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The historical appendix to my SEP entry (Bradley 2014) owes much to Teddy’s prompting.

  2. 2.

    This starting point immediately betrays my allegiance: I am approaching this topic from the point of view of philosophy and formal epistemology, rather than from a more purely mathematical position. If I were committed to the latter, I would prefer to talk in terms of lower previsions or sets of desirable gambles, and if I did so, I would perhaps be less bothered by dilation. It really does seem that dilation, if it is a problem at all, is a problem for a credal set approach rather than other nearby formal frameworks. See Gregory Wheeler’s contribution to this volume for more discussion of the alternatives, and also Augustin et al. (2014) and Troffaes and De Cooman (2014).

  3. 3.

    For more on characterising the exact nature of dilation, and the circumstances under which it occurs, see Herron et al. (1994), Seidenfeld and Wasserman (1993), Pedersen and Wheeler (2014), Herron et al. (1997), Pedersen and Wheeler (2015), Pedersen and Wheeler (2019), and Nielsen and Stewart (2021).

  4. 4.

    One might think that it should be \(\left \{\frac {1}{16},\dots ,\frac {15}{16}\right \}\) instead. Whether or not we demand convexity won’t make a difference in what follows, and the interval is a slightly neater notation.

  5. 5.

    As we’ll see, I think this way of talking—taking \(\mathbb {Q}(B)\) to be an adequate representation of your confidence in B—is problematic, but let’s roll with it for now.

  6. 6.

    I don’t think many would balk at Good’s modest assumptions in the case of a finite partition. As Kadane et al. (2008) point out, countable additivity is required for the result to hold in the infinite case, and, in the context of the current volume, it would be remiss of me not to point out that that is not a principle that enjoys universal acceptance.

  7. 7.

    But see Kadane et al. (2008), Grünwald and Halpern (2004), Bradley and Steele (2016), and Pedersen and Wheeler (2015).

  8. 8.

    Although Bradley and Steele (2014) argue that the alternatives are no better.

  9. 9.

    See Pedersen and Wheeler (2014) for a more sophisticated discussion of dilation and irrelevance.

  10. 10.

    This is one point at which it is clear that my main target is the pro-precise probability crew, rather than, the anti-pointwise-conditioning posse.

  11. 11.

    Or better yet—to avoid what (Easwaran 2014) calls the “numerical fallacy”—it is the whole probability space (including a representation of the algebra of events) that captures your epistemic state.

  12. 12.

    For example White (2010) makes this argument, and Topey (2012) discusses it carefully.

  13. 13.

    This, in essence, is the notion of “informativeness” from De Cooman (2005).

  14. 14.

    One could define similar sets for other notions of “full belief” derived from probabilities, for example using a Lockean threshold, or a stability theory approach (Leitgeb 2014, 2017). For more on the relationship between conditionalisation and sets of full beliefs, see Gärdenfors (1988, Chap. 8).

  15. 15.

    Stewart and Nielsen (this volume) also discuss this kind of approach to measuring the size of credal sets. For another approach to uncertainty roughly in this vein, see Chambers and Melkonyan (2007).

  16. 16.

    Δ and Φ have been chosen as labels for the partitions in order to be mnemonic: Δ is the dilating partition, Φ is the finer partition.

  17. 17.

    Here and throughout the logarithms are base 2 logarithms, and by convention \(0\log 0 = 0\).

  18. 18.

    This essentially follows from the fact that H(L|M) < H(L) for random variables L,M.

  19. 19.

    We could then write \(AU(\mathbb {P},\varDelta )\) as \(\overline {H}(\mathbb {P},\varDelta )\).

  20. 20.

    The lower bound is attained at, for example \(p(B) = \frac {1}{16}\) where \(H(p,\varDelta ) = -\frac {1}{16}\log {\frac {1}{16}} - \frac {15}{16}\log {\frac {15}{16}}\). As p(B) tends to 0, H(p, Δ) tends to 0.

  21. 21.

    Lower bound attained at, for instance \(p(BL)=\frac {1}{32}\). As p(BL) tends to zero, H(p, Φ) tends to one.

  22. 22.

    As \( \underline {\mathbb {Q}}(B)\) tends to 0, \(CSU(\mathbb {Q},\varDelta )\) tends to infinity.

  23. 23.

    There is a slight abuse of notation here, since p(−|L) is actually a member of \(\mathbb {Q}\) rather than \(\mathbb {Q}_L\). I do things this way to emphasise what’s going on. In any case, since conditionalisation is rigid, for all \(p\in \mathbb {Q}_L\), we have p(X|L) = p(X) for all X.

References

  • Augustin, T., Coolen, F.P.A., De Cooman, G., and M.C.M. Troffaes. eds. 2014. Introduction to imprecise probabilities. Hoboken: John Wiley and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, S. 2014. Imprecise probabilities. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Zalta, E.N. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, S., and K. Steele. 2014. Uncertainty, learning and the “problem” of dilation. Erkenntnis 79:1287–1303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, S., and K. Steele. 2016. Can free evidence be bad? value of information for the imprecise probabilist. Philosophy of Science 83:1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bronevich, A., and G.J. Klir. 2010. Measures of uncertainty for imprecise probabilities: an axiomatic approach. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning 51:365–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cha, S.-H. 2007. Comprehensive survey on distance/similarity measures between probability density functions. International Journal of Mathematical Models and Methods in Applied Sciences 1:300–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, R.G., and T. Melkonyan. 2007. Degree of imprecision: geometric and algorithmic approaches. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning 45:106–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cozman, F. 2012. Sets of probability distributions, independence and convexity. Synthese 186:577–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Cooman, G. 2005. Belief models: an order-theoretic investigation. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 45:5–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easwaran, K. 2014. Regularity and hyperreal credences. Philosophical Review 123:1–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gong, R., and X.-L. Meng. 2017. Judicious judgment meets unsettling update: Dilation, sure loss and simpson’s paradox. arXiv:1712.08946v1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I.J. 1967. On the principle of total evidence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17:319–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, I.J. 1974. A little learning can be dangerous. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25:340–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünwald, P.D., and J.Y. Halpern. 2004. When ignorance is bliss. In Proceedings of the Twentieth Conference on Uncertainty in AI, 226–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. 1988. Knowledge in flux: modeling the dynamics of epistemic states. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, C., and M.G. Titelbaum. 2015. Intuitive dilation? Thought 4:252–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herron, T., Seidenfeld, T., and L. Wasserman. 1994. The extent of dilation of sets of probabilities and the asymptotics of robust bayesian inference. In PSA: proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, 250–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herron, T., Seidenfeld, T., and L. Wasserman. 1997. Divisive conditioning: further results on dilation. Philosophy of Science 64(3):411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J.M. 2010. A defense of imprecise credence in inference and decision. Philosophical Perspectives 24:281–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadane, J.B., Schervish, M.J., and T. Seidenfeld. 2008. Is ignorance bliss? Journal of Philosophy CV:5–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klir, G.J. 1999. Uncertainty and information measures for imprecise probabilities: An overview. In Proceedings of the first ISIPTA meeting.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klir, G.J. 2006. Uncertainty and information: foundations of generalized information theory. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. 2014. The stability theory of belief. The Philosophical Review 123:131–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. 2017. The stability of belief: an essay in rationality and coherence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mork, J.C. 2013. Uncertainty, credal sets and second order probability. Synthese 190:353–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, M., and R. Stewart. 2021. Counterexamples to some characterizations of dilation. Erkenntnis 86(5), 1107–1118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pedersen, A.P., and G. Wheeler. 2014. Demystifying dilation. Erkenntnis 79:1305–1342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pedersen, A.P., and G. Wheeler. 2015. Dilation, disintegrations, and delayed decisions. In ISIPTA 2015 proceedings, 227–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pedersen, A.P., and G. Wheeler. 2019. Dilation and asymmetric relevance. In Proceedings of international symposium on imprecise probabilities: theories and applications (ISIPTA 2019), 324–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidenfeld, T., and L. Wasserman. 1993. Dilation for sets of probabilities. Annals of Statistics 21:1139–1154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. 2011. Resiliency, propensities and causal necessity. In Philosophy of probability: contemporary readings, ed. Eagle, A., 529–536. Milton Park: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Topey, B. 2012. Coin flips, credences and the reflection principle. Analysis 72:478–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Troffaes, M., and G. de Cooman. 2014. Lower previsions. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. 2010. Evidential symmetry and mushy credence. In Oxford studies in epistemology, eds. Szabo Gendler, T., and J. Hawthorne, 161–186. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bradley, S. (2022). Dilation and Informativeness. In: Augustin, T., Cozman, F.G., Wheeler, G. (eds) Reflections on the Foundations of Probability and Statistics. Theory and Decision Library A:, vol 54. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-15436-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics