Skip to main content

Informative Models: Idealization and Abstraction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 50))

Abstract

Mauricio Suárez and Agnes Bolinska apply the tools of communication theory to scientific modeling in order to characterize the informational content of a scientific model. They argue that when represented as a communication channel, a model source conveys information about its target, and that such representations are therefore appropriate whenever modeling is employed for informational gain. They then extract two consequences. First, the introduction of idealizations is akin in informational terms to the introduction of noise in a signal; for in an idealization we introduce ‘extraneous’ elements into the model that have no correlate in the target. Second, abstraction in a model is informationally equivalent to equivocation in the signal; for in an abstraction we “neglect” in the model certain features that obtain in the target. They conclude that it becomes possible in principle to quantify idealization and abstraction in informative models, although precise absolute quantification will be difficult to achieve in practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    So is the concomitant terminology of ‘sources’ and ‘targets’ (Suárez 2004); yet, for reasons that will become apparent, it is best for the purposes of this article to refer to representational vehicles and targets, to aptly distinguish them from the terms employed in information theory.

  2. 2.

    See Bolinska (2015) for an application of these notions in the philosophy of science.

  3. 3.

    In fact, a 1–1 copy of the target—as in Borges’ (1954) beautiful parable—would be a 100% informative ‘channel’ and, yet, a perfectly useless model.

  4. 4.

    Indeed one of us (Bolinska 2016) has explicitly understood models as tools for conveying information, identifying the features responsible for their informativeness. See also the discussion of ‘objectivity’ in Suárez (2004, forthcoming).

  5. 5.

    Our use of the terms is inspired by the definitions in Thomson-Jones (2005) and Weisberg (2007); and is reflected most precisely in those used in Pero and Suárez (2016).

  6. 6.

    More recently, Pero and Suárez (2016), Suárez and Pero (2019) and Suárez (forthcoming) contain an extended historical discussion of this example that corrects some philosophical misconceptions.

  7. 7.

    It is actually worse than that: contrary to assumptions billiard balls are not perfectly elastic, but of course experience minor energy loss in the form of heat in collisions; but then again neither are gas molecules perfectly elastic, since they also experience loss of (kinetic) energy in collision. See the discussion in Pero and Suárez (2016, pp. 75–76).

  8. 8.

    Although, certainly, these assumptions can be contested. But nothing much hinges on the particular values. The only claim needed for the present proposal to go through is that there are some values for these probability distributions—whether they are within our reach to know is not essential. As Dretske points out (1981, p. 55) the probability distributions that go into communication theory, and in particular the conditional probabilities in the definition of equivocation, are objective, and may be very hard to get to know.

  9. 9.

    For instance, one could imagine a model where the colour of the elastic ‘billiard’ balls is taken to represent the initial velocity of each corresponding molecule in the gas, with purple representing the larger speeds and red representing the smaller speeds and all the other colours representing intermediate speed ranges in the prescribed order in the electromagnetic visible spectrum. Such model would not be very useful, but it is perfectly possible, for any given gas.

  10. 10.

    Determinism is also arguably an assumption for systems of billiard balls, if we assume an initial probability distribution over the dynamical variables of interest (as is done, e.g. in the tradition of the method of arbitrary functions). We shall ignore this complication and assume deterministic Newtonian dynamics.

References

  • Bailer-Jones, D. (2003). When scientific models represent. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17(1), 59–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boesch, B. (2017). There is a special problem of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 84(5), 970–981.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinska, A. (2013). Epistemic representation, informativeness and the aim of faithful representation. Synthese, 190(2), 219–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinska, A. (2015). Epistemic representation in science and beyond. PhD Dissertation. Toronto: University of Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinska, A. (2016). Successful visual epistemic representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 56, 153–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borges, J. L. (1954). Del rigor en la ciencia. In Historia universal de la infamia: Obras completas 3, Buenos Aires: Emecé Editores, pp. 131–132. Translated as On Exactitude in Science. In Jorge Luis Borges: Collected Fictions, London: Penguin, 1998, p. 325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N. (1920). Physics: The elements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2007). Scientific representation, interpretation and surrogative reasoning. Philosophy of Science, 74(1), 48–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 742–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2009). An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese, 172(2), 269–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. (1966). Models and analogies in science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luciano, F. (2007). In defence of the veridical nature of semantic information. The European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 3(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKay, D. (2003). Information theory, inference, and learning algorithms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2009). Missing the world. Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis, 70(1), 29–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M., & Morrison, M. (Eds.). (1999). Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pero, F., & Suárez, M. (2016). Varieties of misrepresentation and isomorphism. European Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 6(1), 71–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pierce, J. (1961). An introduction to information theory: Symbols, signals and noise. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A., & Piccinini, G. (2010). Information without truth. Metaphilosophy, 41(3), 313–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. (1948). The mathematical theory of communication. The Bell System Technical Journal, 27(3), 379–423; 27(4), 623–656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (forthcoming). Inference and scientific representation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 767–779.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M (Ed.). (2009). Fictions in science: Philosophical essays on modeling and idealization. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M., & Pero, F. (2019). The representational semantic conception. Philosophy of Science, 86(2), 344–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1962). Models of data. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science: Proceedings of the 1960 international congress (pp. 252–261). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (2001). Twilight of the perfect model model. Erkenntnis, 55(3), 393–415.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2005). Idealization and abstraction: A framework. In M. Thomson-Jones & N. Cartwright (Eds.), Idealization XII: Correcting the model-idealization and abstraction in the sciences (pp. 173–218). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. Journal of Philosophy, 104(12), 639–659.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Mauricio Suárez would like to thank Tarja Knuuttila and the audience at the 2016 Valparaiso workshop on Models and Idealizations in Science for their comments and reactions, as well as financial support from the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation project PGC2018 099423. Agnes Bolinska would like to thank Anna Alexandrova and Joseph D. Martin for helpful feeback. 

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mauricio Suárez .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Suárez, M., Bolinska, A. (2021). Informative Models: Idealization and Abstraction. In: Cassini, A., Redmond, J. (eds) Models and Idealizations in Science. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 50. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-65802-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics