Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Numanities - Arts and Humanities in Progress ((NAHP,volume 14))

  • 158 Accesses

Abstract

Communication and empirical “principles”. Communication with historical “partners”. “Multi-perspectivity”. Inter cultural communication. Visuality, audiality, and tactility. Deconstruction as communication. Communication based on physiological data. Discourse as power.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Kačerauskas (2008) for an extensive discussion.

  2. 2.

    Another name (Greek) for this procedure is epoché.

  3. 3.

    For example, a claim that “information is transmitted only by means of language” is negated by showing that information can be transmitted by a gesture or facial expression. Yet, since gestures and expressions are a part of language we encounter empirical limits.

  4. 4.

    Its truth does not necessarily correspond to reality. Depending on which theory of truth we maintain, there can be other criteria of truth—utility, evidence, coherence, and praxis.

  5. 5.

    Which, in part, corresponds to the cybernetic school.

  6. 6.

    This might be called a ‘super-view’ as an aspect of metacommunication, although as a survey of totality a super-view is impossible. Rather, it is necessary as an appearance of any phenomenon or even environment, which brings to mind the dialectic of activity and passivity. Active is not only phenomenon, emerging in a passive environment, but the latter is also active, “ejecting” or “exiling” from itself a passive phenomenon. Such passive-active dialectic makes sense of intolerance and even the repression of outstanding creators. The history of art as well as the sciences speaks loudly with examples of such repressions, which, in their mildest form, is non-acceptance, the most famous case being Vincent van Gogh. The repressive activity of the environment is a strategic part of self-preservation (passive one?). Conversely, the passivity of a creator in case of the rejection of their work (purportedly, the work must defend itself without the aid of the author) is an active aspect of such creativity.

  7. 7.

    However, there are discussions about a common, communal archetypical experience, inherent in the “collective unconscious” (Jung 1991), and with which empiricism has nothing in common, and would not tolerate such a claim.

  8. 8.

    Kant (1999) was concerned with the incompatibility between empiricism and scientific, universal necessity, which resulted in the thesis of synthetic a priori judgments.

  9. 9.

    The primacy, even the metaphysics of empiricism, did not persuade Lazarsfeld’s students to remain his followers. Thus, the question of empirical communication returns us to the issue of communication between teacher and student.

  10. 10.

    Here, we should recall Roger Bacon.

  11. 11.

    Famous thinkers such as Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Hegel, and even Kant, are considered to be rationalists.

  12. 12.

    This reputation was due mainly to the British and Scottish philosophers, Francis Bacon, John Locke and David Hume.

  13. 13.

    The mental experiment of Einstein could be regarded as a rational imitation of experiment. This does not mean that to support a theory there is no need to discover empirical data, however theories are created as logical and economic standards.

  14. 14.

    Let us recall the doctrine of recollection (anamnesis) of Plato, the father of rationalism. Upon seeing (confirming by senses) a friend, we recall the idea of friendship. An opposite example comes from the founder of empiricism, Aristotle, who claims that any individual (primary substance) is understood in a context of common features (secondary substance).

  15. 15.

    This reminds us of Buber’s (2000) “I-You” relationship.

  16. 16.

    In Heidegger’s words, Dasein.

  17. 17.

    Both aspects of the history of communication are clarified by Peters (1999).

  18. 18.

    Let us recall his funeral eulogy.

  19. 19.

    They were realized by the teachings of the sophists.

  20. 20.

    We mentioned in another context that metaphor cannot be translated without creating a semantic deficit.

  21. 21.

    Let us recall the late Wittgenstein’s (1990) question whether a diffused image is something that we do not need?

  22. 22.

    Another way to consider this is that it could be an imaginative variety or even a variety of worldviews.

  23. 23.

    For more about rating mind set and media similarity, see Bourdieu (2011).

  24. 24.

    This is the case in Lithuanian politics where social democrats destroyed small business by disproportionally taxing it before joining the EU.

  25. 25.

    The rules of education in North Korea and South Korea.

  26. 26.

    Education rules in Netherlands and Germany.

  27. 27.

    Educational rules in state and private institutions.

  28. 28.

    Merleau-Ponty (1968).

  29. 29.

    After Copernicus “recalled” Aristarchus’s heliocentric system, most astronomers continued to use the geocentric system for a further 150 years. This has less to do with a lack of open communication, as much as with some visible details of the world—the returning movements of the planets, which until Kepler was better explained by the geocentric view of the followers of Ptolemy. In other words, an encounter with things determined by a perspective. We return to the phenomenological view as a channel for various perspectives.

  30. 30.

    The somewhat unique question is whether or not the Sovietization of the Baltic states was colonialism. In this regard Epp Annus (2012) explores several problems. First, colonialism is a Western phenomenon and Russia hardly represents Western culture. Second, colonialism is inseparable from capitalism, while the Soviet system rejected the latter. Third, colonialism encounters “primitive” cultures which can be easily assimilated, while in the case of so-called Soviet colonization local culture was resistant, and even attractive (one aspect of such attraction—its being Western).

  31. 31.

    The first impetus to change Western culture in the face of another culture appeared after the Crusades of the medieval period. It is paradoxical that during the Crusades (which were completely intolerant, even with respect to culturally similar cultures, such as Byzantium) reclaimed not only lands, but also some of the essential components of Western culture, e.g. the scientific heritage of Aristotle, including his rhetorical and metaphysical works. Yet, in this case, Flusser’s rule of communication is valid: Aristotle is reclaimed not by taking him away from Arabic culture, but by sharing his work.

  32. 32.

    It is possible to speak of varied types of democracy in ancient Greece (democracy with slavery), in Russia (democracy of leaders), in Central and East Europe (pendulum democracy) and more. In this case we have a minor multi-perspectivism in multi-layered Western culture.

  33. 33.

    In being a translator I will add a translation of your part of this work—and not only that of Heidegger’s work, Being and Time.

  34. 34.

    This is how Benjamin reflects on Hölderlin’s literal translation: “it is self-evident how greatly fidelity in reproducing the form impedes the rendering of the sense. Thus, no case for literalness can be based on a desire to retain the meaning. <…> translation must in large measure refrain from wanting to communicate something, from rendering the sense, and in this the original is important to it only insofar as it has already relieved the translator and his translation of the effort of assembling and expressing what is to be conveyed. <…> On the other hand, as regards the meaning, the language of a translation can-in fact, must-let itself go, so that it gives voice to the intentio of the original not as reproduction but as harmony, as a supplement to the language in which it expresses itself, as its own kind of intentio” (1969: 78–79). Thus, translation must be a dimension to expand the original sense and not to be limited by it. Literal translation leads to limitation. The difficulties of literal translation are the lack of communicative channel, neither between different languages nor cultures. To the contrary, communication possibility between them is enhanced by their disappearance and disproportion.

  35. 35.

    Yet, Hölderlin is the favourite poet of Heidegger who is responsible for enhancing the reputation of the poet (and not a translator). In this case, a philosopher served as a publicist of a poet. First, this suggests the commonality between poetry and philosophy. Second, philosophy and poetry are mutually founding: poetry signifies being which is deliberated by philosophy. This is not to say that between them there is a communication channel. To the contrary, any communication between them rests on a common existential region.

  36. 36.

    Let us recall Heidegger’s student, Arendt’s (1958) “un-ease” (Un-ruhe, nec-otium, a-scholia).

  37. 37.

    For example, the representatives of larger nations (or cultures) invariably know less languages, and as a result are less communicative.

  38. 38.

    According to Flusser, codification is done in the name of communication, i.e. in the name of a meaningless world and life to be persuaded, as well as to silence death (2007: 259–260).

  39. 39.

    This is attested by places in encyclopaedia or sacred writings where the creation is most likely to become closed and not open to communication.

  40. 40.

    This is an analogy with Aristotle’s unmoved mover. Yet, metaphor is a minor mover or concretizer, by not being beyond, but in the heart of this world—language. Aristotle was concerned with metaphor in the context of rhetoric, which is the more convincing. The more sensational is the figure of language. Metaphor can be interpreted as Aristotle’s poetics of cleansing of the soul in tragic context.

  41. 41.

    For more on this see Kačerauskas (2006).

  42. 42.

    Let us recall Husserl’s return to the idea of things themselves, which you, Algis, in your work with David Stewart, Exploring Phenomenology (Mickunas and Stewart 1990), have articulated. Heidegger (1996) also adheres to this position, regarding things as world signs of our existence.

  43. 43.

    Heidegger calls this inbeing. We are not only, and not somewhat close to the world, as much as we are in it. Senses are what make us unworldly.

  44. 44.

    Let us recall Greimas (1987a, b) who is also important as a proliferator of semiotics.

  45. 45.

    Trace is another theme in Lévinas philosophy (1979) where it is predominantly ethical. It can be said that shibboleth is a trace of Lévinas’ ethics in the region of Derrida’s deconstructed morality.

  46. 46.

    The absence of a trace is analogous to the non-being of metaphor.

  47. 47.

    Unmasking can be investigated in analogy to deconstruction.

  48. 48.

    After Nietzsche, who has mortified metaphysics (Heidegger 1972), it means superfluous activity.

  49. 49.

    The same can be said of Heidegger’s (1996) applied destruction. Primarily, Plato, Aristotle, and Descartes are brought into a specific space wherein illuminated by existential ontology, they are destroyed.

  50. 50.

    One version concerning orders is the Russian use of swearwords in communicating orders—which was a factor in the Russian victory in the Second World War. It would seem that the limit of swear words is equivalent to the signals of other creatures. Of course, communication by the use of swear words does not mean clarity—even if they are simple and unambiguous. The same historical swear words can be used in different situations and understood differently.

  51. 51.

    For example, the absence of diplomatic ties between Poland and Lithuania between the two world wars was a clear message: Return Vilnius.

  52. 52.

    More recently there is a discussion about the cultural turn toward visuality (Mitchell 1994), or about the surge of visual culture (Manovich 2001).

  53. 53.

    More seeing than hearing, smelling, touching or tasting.

  54. 54.

    Semantic communication equally exploits sense difference. The mentioned difference of J. Derrida is related etymologically to difference.

  55. 55.

    Let us look at the paradox of toleration: do we have to be tolerant of non-tolerance, and if non-tolerance for non-tolerance abolishes tolerance? Put another way, does the murder of murderers justify murder?

  56. 56.

    It is said that the gays are best conversants with women.

  57. 57.

    Recall Baudrillard’s (2016) hyper-reality.

  58. 58.

    The phenomenon of insanity and the demarcation of madness from specific institutions without medical aid is another theme discussed elsewhere by Foucault (1972). The theme of madness is intertwined with that of creativity (Schopenhauer 1969), not only because mad persons and creative workers are primarily categorised as disturbers of the normal order. Every creative worker is mad since they aim at the unknown and novel, and in doing so blaze new trails for the community.

  59. 59.

    The expulsion of the most creative and talented members of society in democratic states has an old tradition. In the case of Anaxagoras his thinking “went too far” and threatened to disrupt the stability of the Athenian order.

  60. 60.

    Whether true or not, scientists are often accused of appropriating their student’s (doctoral) research and texts.

  61. 61.

    This is illustrated by interactive media with the possibility for readers’ commentaries. Yet, the amount of commentaries (even if negative) indicate the importance of a topic. Such communication also demonstrates provocations that are required for creativity.

  62. 62.

    This illustrates that such instruments as classification used to control the sciences prevent interdisciplinary studies, despite pronouncements to the contrary.

  63. 63.

    For example, Heidegger destroys Aristotelianism by involving the resources of existential ontology. J. Derrida acts similarly with respect to Platonism, even if he claims to be neutral with respect to any discourse. This pretended neutralism hides meta-discoursivity: it is possible to deconstruct by a suspicious rejection of any discourse. In this case suspicion appeals to another—Marxist or Frankfurt school—discourse; but these traditions also must be destructed and deconstructed. Is this not an infinite regress criticised by Aristotle?

References

  • Annus, Epp. 2012. The problem of Soviet colonialism in the Baltics. Journal of Baltic Studies 43 (1): 21–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baudrillard, Jean. 2016. Symbolic Exchange and Death. Translated by I.H. Grant. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Walter. 1969. Illuminations. Translated by H. Zohn. New York: Schocken Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, Pierre. 2011. Sur la Television. http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=vcc6AEpjdcY.

  • Buber, Martin. 2000. I and Thou. Translated by R.G. Smith. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 1990. Gender Trouble. Routledge: Chapman and Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrilho, Manuel M. 1996. Rhetoric and perspectivism. Revue Internationale de Philosophy 28 (3): 59–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1992. From Shibboleth: For Paul Celan. Acts of Literature, 370–413. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1997. Of Grammatology. Translated by G.Ch. Spivak. Baltimore & London: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, Paul. 1993. Against Method. London, New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Florida, Richard. 2002. The Rise of the Creative Class: And How It’s Transforming Work, Leisure, Community and Everyday Life. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flusser, Vilém. 2007. „Vorlesungen zur Kommunikologie.“ In Kommunikologie, 233–235. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1971. L’ordre du discours. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1972. Madness and Civilization; a History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Görner, Rüdiger. 1995. The poetics of historical perspectivism. Modern Language Review 90: 234–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greimas, Algirdas J. 1987a. De l’imperfection. Périgueux: Fanlac.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greimas, Algirdas J. 1987b. On Meaning: Selected Writings in Semiotic Theory. Translated by P.J. Perron and F.H. Collins. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1972. Nietzsche’s Wort “Gott ist tot.” In M. Heidegger. Holzwege, 193–247. Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1996. Being and Time. Translated by J. Stambough. New York: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 2000. A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1970. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Translated by D. Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray, Luce. 1985. This Sex Which Is not One. New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, Carl G. 1991. The archetypes and the collective unconscious. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kačerauskas, Tomas. 2006. Filosofinė poetika [Philosophical Poetics]. Vilnius: Versus aureus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kačerauskas, Tomas. 2008. Tikrovė ir kūryba: kultūros fenomenologijos metmenys [Reality and Creation: Sketches of Cultural Phenomenology]. Vilnius: Technika.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kačerauskas, Tomas. 2011. Individas istorinėje bendrijoje: kultūrinės regionalistikos apmatai [An Individual in Historical Community: Sketches of Cultural Regionalistics]. Vilnius: Technika.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kačerauskas, Tomas, and Tautvydas Vėželis. 2016. Šiapusybės regionai: 50 Heideggerio filosofijos klausimų [Regions of Dasein: 50 Questions About Heidegger’s Philosophy]. Vilnius: Technika.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1999. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by P. Guyer and A.W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kossler, Matthias. 1995. Philosophy of perspectivism: Truth and perspective in Kant, Hegel and Nietzsche. Kant-Studien 86 (4): 467–470.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lazarsfeld, Paul F. 1972. Qualitative Analysis: Historical and Critical Essays. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévinas, Emmanuel. 1979. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Translated by A. Lingis. Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1964. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. London: Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manovich, Lev. 2001. The Language of New Media. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1991. One-dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLuhan, Marshall. 1964. Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1962. Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by C. Smith. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1964. Eye and Mind. Translated by C. Dallery. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1968. The Visible and the Invisible. Translated by A. Lingis. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mickunas, Algis, and David Stewart. 1990. Exploring Phenomenology. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, William J.T. 1994. Picture Theory. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1998. On the Genealogy of Morality. Translated by C. Diethe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2002. Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by J. Norman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ozmon, Howard A., and Samuel M. Craver. 2008. Philosophical Foundations of Education. New York: Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, Jacob V. 2015. The potential of perspectivism for science education. Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (5): 531–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, John D. 1999. Speaking into the Air: A History of the Idea of Communication. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1990. Sophist. Translated by W.S. Cobb. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1989. Logik der Forschung. Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramos, Alcida R. 2015. The politics of perspectivism. Annual Review of Anthropology 41: 481–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schenck, David. 1985. Merleau-Ponty on perspectivism, with references to Nietzsche. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46 (2): 307–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, Arthur. 1969. The World as Will and Representation. Translated by R.B. Haldane and J. Kemp. New York: Dover Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Walter J. 1994. Perspectivism—Aquinas and Nietzsche on intellect and will. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68 (4): 451–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1990. Tractatus logico-philosophicus. In Wittgenstein’s Werkausgabe. Bd. 1. Frankfurt am Mein: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tomas Kačerauskas .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kačerauskas, T., Mickūnas, A. (2020). Perspectiveness and Discoursiveness. In: In Between Communication Theories Through One Hundred Questions. Numanities - Arts and Humanities in Progress, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-41106-0_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics