Skip to main content

“Knowledge” in Context: A Conundrum

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 105 Accesses

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Philosophy ((BRIEFSPHILOSOPH))

Abstract

Contextualism is the thesis that the truth-conditions of knowledge-ascribing and knowledge-denying sentences can vary depending on certain features of the context of the knowledge attributor. According to a recent objection labelled “the factivity problem”, contextualism, if combined with the principle of factivity and with the principle of closure, would turn out to be an inconsistent theory. In this chapter are presented the contextualist stance—from both a semantic and an epistemic point of view—the argument of the factivity problem and the implications of the issue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The characterization of indexicality that we will use is the following: a linguistic expression is indexical iff its content depends on the features of its context of utterance. This characterization of indexicality is due to MacFarlane (2009), who distinguishes it from the semantic phenomenon of context-sensitivity—a linguistic expression is context-sensitive iff its extension depends on the features of its context of utterance. Uncontroversial examples of indexical expressions in this sense are those belonging to Cappelen and Lepore’s basic set (2005): pure indexicals like “I” and “here”, true demonstratives like “this” and “that”, personal pronouns like “he” and “she”.

  2. 2.

    For an analysis of the different features that may determine the epistemic standard in a context see Baumann (2016: 20–31).

  3. 3.

    The term “invariantism” is generally used to label the position of those who deny contextualism with regard to a certain term. See Unger (1984). Here we will use this expression to denote those who claim that there is one and only one epistemic standard for “know”.

  4. 4.

    We slightly modified DeRose’s example since in its original formulation it is a first person case (i.e. a case where the ascriber corresponds to the person to whom is ascribed knowledge) and this sort of examples is consistent with subject-sensitive invariantism, a view that like classical invariantism claims that “know” expresses the same relation at every context of use, but unlike it holds that whether a subject “knows that p may be determined in part by practical facts about the subject’s environment” (Stanley 2005: 85; see also Hawthorne (2004: 157 ff). On this point see Blackson (2004). Third person cases (where the ascriber does not correspond to the person to whom knowledge is ascribed) provide, instead, a better ground to illustrate the contextualist thesis. For an illustration and a defence of the contextualist’s strategy appealing to this kind of cases see DeRose (2009: 47–79). See also Pynn (2017) for discussion.

  5. 5.

    On this point see also Leardi and Vassallo (2017). Notice that the invariantists (or, more precisely, non-sceptical invariantists) have proposed arguments to show that (10) is true simpliciter and that, instead of being false in the latter scenario, it would be conversationally inappropriate. On this point see Rysiew (2001), Black (2008), and Pritchard (2010). For a contextualist response to these arguments see Baumann (2011) and Leardi and Vassallo (2017).

  6. 6.

    According to MacFarlane the argument from cases (like DeRose’s Bank case or Cohen’s Airport case) would not yield the alleged result: indeed, if this sort of argument straightforwardly supports the view that knowledge ascriptions are context-sensitive (i.e. that their truth-value depend upon their context of utterance) it would not clearly provide evidence for their indexicality. See MacFarlane (2009) for discussion.

  7. 7.

    Pritchard moves an objection against contextualism along these lines, even though he limits his remark to contextualism as a semantic thesis without considering the possible metaphysical implications of the view. Pritchard, indeed, observes that one might think that, since according to a certain reading of contextualism the epistemic standards can be hierarchically ordered, in the end, the only epistemic standard worth of epistemological concern is that employed by the sceptic (2005: 25). For a reply to Pritchard’s objection see Leardi and Vassallo (2017).

  8. 8.

    The most notable exceptions to the acceptation of the closure principle are those of Nozick (1981) and Dretske (1970, 1971, 2014).

  9. 9.

    For example, this version of the closure principle strongly connects the belief that q with the deduction from p, avoiding an objection according which one might come to know q on a completely independent basis. For an analysis of the closure principle see Vogel (1990), Hawthorne (2014) and Luper (2016).

References

  • Ayer AJ (1956) The problem of knowledge. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1970). Other minds. In: Urmson JO, Warnock GJ (eds) Philosophical papers. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 76–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumann P (2008) Contextualism and the factivity problem. Philos Phenomenological Res 76:580–602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumann P (2011) WAM: why worry? Philos Pap 40(2):155–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumann P (2016) Epistemic contextualism. A defense. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi C, Vassallo N (2005) Epistemological contextualism: a semantic perspective. In: Dey A, Kokinov B, Leake D, Turner R (eds) Modeling and using context. Springer, Berlin, pp 41–54

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Black T (2008) A warranted-assertability defense of a Moorean response to skepticism. Acta Anal 23(3):187–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackson T (2004) An invalid argument for contextualism. Philos Phenomenological Res 68(2):344–345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann M (2014) Knowledge and presuppositions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brendel E (2005) Why contextualists cannot know they are right: self-refuting implications of contextualism. Acta Anal 20(2):38–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brendel E (2009) Contextualism, relativism and factivity: analysing ‘knowledge’ after the new linguistic turn in epistemology. Pub Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Soc 11:404–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Brendel E (2014) Contextualism, relativism, and the semantics of knowledge ascriptions. Philos Stud 168(1):101–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner A (2004) The elusive virtues of contextualism. Philos Stud 118:401–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen H, Lepore E (2005) Insensitive semantics: a defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Blackwell, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S (1986) Knowledge and context. J Philos 83(10):574–583

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S (1987) Knowledge, context, and social standards. Synthese 73(1):3–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S (1988) How to be a fallibilist. Philos Perspect 2:91–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S (1999) Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philos Perspect 13(s13):57–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S (2000) Contextualism and skepticism. Philos Issues 10(1):94–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K (1992) Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philos Phenomenological Res 52(4):913–929

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K (1995) Solving the skeptical problem. Philos Rev 104(1):1–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K (2009) The case for contextualism: knowledge, skepticism, and context, vol 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K (2017) The appearance of ignorance: knowledge, skepticism, and context, vol 2. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R (1985) Discourse on method. In: Cottingham J, Stoothoff R, Murdoch D (eds) The philosophical writing of descartes, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 111–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1970) Epistemic operators. J Philos 67(24):1007–1023

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1971) Conclusive reasons. Australas J Philos 49(1):1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (2014) The case against closure. In: Steup M, Turri J, Sosa E (eds) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, pp 27–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel M (2004) What’s wrong with contextualism, and a non–contextualist resolution of the skeptical paradox. Erkenntnis 61:203–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman R (2001) Skeptical problems, contextualist solutions. Philos Stud 103:61–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Hannon M (2013) ‘Knows’ entails truth. J Philos Res 38:349–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne J (2004) Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne J (2014) The case for closure. In: Steup M, Turri J, Sosa E (eds) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, pp 40–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1960) Treatise of human nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa JJ (2017) Contextualizing knowledge. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jäger C (2012) Contextualism and the knowledge norm of assertion. Analysis 72(3):491–498

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kallestrup J (2005) Contextualism between scepticism and common-sense. Grazer Philosophische Stud 69(1):247–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D (1989) Demonstratives. In: Almog J, Perry J, Wettstein H (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 481–563

    Google Scholar 

  • Kompa N (2005) The semantics of knowledge attributions. Acta Anal 20(1):16–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kompa N (2014) Knowledge in context. Riv Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 5(1):58–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig JL (2009) Assertion, knowledge and lotteries. In: Greenough P, Pritchard D (eds) Williamson on knowledge. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 140–160

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig JL (2011) Norms of assertion. In: Brown J, Cappelen H (eds) Assertion: new philosophical essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 233–250

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey J (2007) Norms of assertion. Nous 41:594–626

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leardi S, Vassallo N (2015) Epistemic contextualism: an inconsistent account for the semantics of “know”? In: Christiansen H, Stojanovic I, Papadopoulos GA (eds) Modelling and using context. Springer, Berlin, pp 302–315

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leardi S, Vassallo N (2017) Scepticism and contextualism. Three objections and three replies. Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 4:953–973

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1996) Elusive knowledge. Australas J Philos 74(4):549–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1975) An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow P (2005) Contextualism and the new linguistic turn in epistemology. In: Preyer G, Peter G (eds) Contextualism in philosophy: knowledge, meaning, and truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 11–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Luper S (2016) Epistemic closure. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/closure–epistemic/

  • MacFarlane J (2009) Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese 166(2):231–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitra I, Weatherson B (2010) Assertion, knowledge, and action. Philos Stud 149(1):99–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm N (1952) Knowledge and belief. Mind 61(242):178–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna R (2017) Pluralism about knowledge. In Coliva A, Pederson N (eds) Epistemic pluralism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, pp 171–199

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1981) Philosophical explanations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard D (2005) Neo-mooreanism versus contextualism. Grazer Philosophische Studien 69(1):1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard D (2010) Contextualism, skepticism, and warranted assertability maneuvers. In: Campbell JK, Rourke MO, Silverstein H (eds) Knowledge and skepticism. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 85–103

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pynn G (2017) The intuitive basis for contextualism. In: Ichikawa JJ (ed) The Routledge handbook of epistemic contextualism. Routledge, New York, pp 32–43

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew P (2001) The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs 35(4):477–514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew P (2016) Epistemic contextualism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/contextualism–epistemology/

  • Rudner R (1953) The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philos Sci 20(1):1–6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sgaravatti D (2013) In conversation with the skeptic: contextualism and the raising of standards. Int J Study Skepticism 3(2):97–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J (2005) Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Steup M (2005) Contextualism and conceptual disambiguation. Acta Anal 20–1(34):3–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger P (1984) Philosophical relativity. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Veber M (2004) Contextualism and semantic ascent. South J Philos 42:261–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel J (1990). Are there counterexamples to the closure principle? In: Roth M, Ross G (eds) Doubting: contemporary perspectives on skepticism. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 13–29

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (1996) Knowing and asserting. Philos Rev 105:489–523

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2001) Comments on Michael Williams’ contextualism, externalism and epistemic standards’. Philos Stud 103(1):25–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2000) Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L, Anscombe GEM, von Wright GH, Paul D (eds) (1969) On certainty. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright C (2005) Contextualism and scepticism: even-handedness, factivity and surreptitiously raising standards. Philoso Q 55:236–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefano Leardi .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Leardi, S., Vassallo, N. (2018). “Knowledge” in Context: A Conundrum. In: Contextualism, Factivity and Closure. SpringerBriefs in Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16155-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics