Skip to main content

Nishida, Aesthetics, and the Limits of Cultural Synthesis

  • Chapter
  • 1069 Accesses

In this chapter, my aim is to give a brief outline of the aesthetics that forms part of the Nishida tetsugaku(Nishida's philosophy) and draw from it a more general lesson. In aesthetics as in the whole of the rest of his philosophy, Nishida has a special value for students of comparative thought. As my Japanese colleagues have told me repeatedly, Nishida was one of the last Japanese to be brought up in what they call the old Japanese way of thinking. What is unique to him is his sustained attempt, carried on at the highest level of philosophical endeavor, to try to articulate his interpretation of experience, an experience formed by Zen and centrally dependent on the ideas of the prajñaparamitāsutras, in terms of categorial frameworks drawn from the western philosophies that so fascinated him. What emerges from this lifelong task is a philosophy that, though articulated in different categorial frameworks, is manifestly unchanged in its essentials.1 It is a philosophy that (I would argue) articulates a view of experience that is simply incommensurable with that which informs the mainstream of western thought, especially as the latter derives from Aristotelian logic. It is a deeplydifferent way of understanding the world and of being human. What makes the case of Nishida so uniquely valuable is precisely that he illuminates this deep difference by pushing western philosophical categories to their limit. In the end, he found that in order to say what he had to say, he had to disagree with western assumptions at their most basic level, including the law of identity and the principle of contradiction, among the bedrock laws of Aristotelian thought.

To reinforce the case for incommensurability, at appropriate points below, I will refer to aesthetic theories developed by western thinkers, especially those with an idealist cast that might at first look quite similar to that of Nishida. The reason for doing so is to demonstrate that in fact the relation between Nishida's view and close western analogues is in fact never, in the last analysis, one of identity. Ultimately, I will suggest that for reasons deep in metaphysics there must remain a final difference between an aesthetic based on Nishida's premises and any based on what I term Aristotelian, individualist assumptions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. Some scholars identify three major phases in Nishida's thought, others four, the latter regarding the emphasis to be found in his last works on the historical world, as sufficient to differentiate this phase from the mu no bashophase. I would argue that this is to a degree a matter of intellectual taste: the categorial framework based on the place of nothingness remains unchanged in the last works though he does place there additional stress on the importance of the historical world — Nishida changes the emphasis rather than radically changing the basic categories of his thought. The earlier changes in Nishida tetsugakuare more radical: those from the pure experience phase to the Fichte-Kant stage, and from the latter to the place of nothingness phase, are much deeper

    Google Scholar 

  2. This statement from the Heart Sutrais typical: “…form is emptiness and the very emptiness is form; emptiness does not differ from form, form does not differ from emptiness; whatever is form, that is emptiness, whatever is emptiness, that is form, the same is true of feelings, perceptions, impulses and consciousness.” Buddhist Wisdom BooksTrans: Edward Conze, London: Allen and Unwin, 1958, p. 81

    Google Scholar 

  3. Early Memoriesin M. Abe (ed.) A Zen Life: D.T. Suzuki Remembered, New York: Weatherhill, 1986, p. 11

    Google Scholar 

  4. AM, pp. 107–108

    Google Scholar 

  5. NRWV, p. 77

    Google Scholar 

  6. The idea that in the context of aesthetic experience emotions are in us but not predicable of us is to be found in R.K. Elliott's Aesthetic Theory and the Experience of Art, 1966, reprinted in H. Osborne (ed.) Aesthetics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972, p. 147. Elliott is following Plato's distinction (Lysis, 217C-218B) between ignorance that is in a person and predica-ble of that person and ignorance that is in a person but not predicable of them

    Google Scholar 

  7. AM, p. 112

    Google Scholar 

  8. AM, p. 15. In An Inquiry into the Good, Nishida uses aesthetic experience as a means to indicate what pure experience is like: “Just like when we become enraptured by exquisite music, forget ourselves and everything around us, and experience the universe as one melodious sound, true reality presents itself in the moment of direct experience.” IG, p. 48

    Google Scholar 

  9. AM, p. 14. See also Nishida's essay Affective feelingin Y. Nitta and H. Tatematsu (eds.) Japanese Phenomenology, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979, pp. 223–247 (a translation of Kanjó from Ishiki no mondai/The Problem of Consciousness, 1920)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Wackenroder: How and in what manner one must regard and use the Works of the Great Artists of Earth for the Well-Being of his Soulin M.H. Schubert (ed. and trans.) Wackenroder's Confessions and Fantasies, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania University Press, 1971, p. 126. The same point is made, for instance, in August Wilhelm Schlegel's Lectures on Belles-lettres and Art (Vorlesungen über schöne Literatur und Kunst), 1801: “In the solemn, steady movement of devotional movement, there is inherent in every instant a sense of harmony and perfection, a unity of existence which to Christians is an image of heavenly bliss,” and in P. LeHuray and J. Day (eds.) Music and Aesthetics in the Eighteenth and Early Nineteenth Centuries, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 195

    Google Scholar 

  11. As he puts it in NRWV: “…the mystical has no use at all in our practical lives. Were religion some kind of special consciousness of privileged persons it would merely be the idle matter of idle men.” p. 115. The same careful and emphatic refusal to identify aesthetic experience with religious experience can be found in the thought of the great Kashmiri aesthetician Abhinavagupta, whose views can be fruitfully compared with those of Nishida on the one hand and relevant western theories on the other. There is an excellent summary of Abhinava's views with full references to primary sources in Chantal Maillard and Oscar Pujol Rasa: El placer estético en la tradición India, Varanasi: Indica, 1999, pp. 88

    Google Scholar 

  12. Edward Bullough ‘Psychical Distance’ as a Factor in Art and an Aesthetic Principle, 1912 reprinted in E.M. Wilkinson (ed.), Aesthetics: Lectures and Essays, Westport (Conn.): Greenwood Press, 1977, pp. 91–130

    Google Scholar 

  13. AM, p. 5

    Google Scholar 

  14. AM, pp. 8–9

    Google Scholar 

  15. AM, p. 185, cf. Kant Critique of Judgment, Analytic of the Beautiful,Third Moment

    Google Scholar 

  16. Nishida stresses the dynamic nature of reality in many places, e.g., “the most immediate, concrete reality for us is a system of self-generating, self-developing experience.” IRSC, p. 64

    Google Scholar 

  17. AM, pp. 15–16 and 162

    Google Scholar 

  18. Novalis: Miscellaneous Observations, para. 17 in M.M. Stoljar (ed. and trans.) Novalis: Philosophical Writings, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997, p. 25

    Google Scholar 

  19. IG, pp. 39–40

    Google Scholar 

  20. AM, p. 19

    Google Scholar 

  21. AM, p. 20

    Google Scholar 

  22. AM, p. 27

    Google Scholar 

  23. AM, loc. cit

    Google Scholar 

  24. IRSC, p. 131

    Google Scholar 

  25. AM, p. 52. The thesis that what we ordinarily call the natural world is a constructed abstraction is present in Nishida's thought from the start, cf. IG, Ch. 12, passim

    Google Scholar 

  26. AM, p. 161

    Google Scholar 

  27. AM, p. 187

    Google Scholar 

  28. IRSC, pp. 145 and 153

    Google Scholar 

  29. AM, p. 33

    Google Scholar 

  30. IRSC, p. 156

    Google Scholar 

  31. AM, p. 47

    Google Scholar 

  32. AM, p. 103

    Google Scholar 

  33. AM, p. 104

    Google Scholar 

  34. AM, p. 26; cf. R.G. Collingwood The Principles of Art, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1938, pp. 20–26

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. Collingwood, op. cit., Ch. XIV, passim

    Google Scholar 

  36. AM, p. 34

    Google Scholar 

  37. AM, p. 35

    Google Scholar 

  38. AM, pp. 35 and 103

    Google Scholar 

  39. AM, p. 164

    Google Scholar 

  40. AM, pp. 98–99; cf. Aristotle Poetics1451b

    Google Scholar 

  41. Friedrich Schlegel Ideaspara. 16 in P. Firchow (trans.) Friedrich Schlegel: Philosophical Fragments, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1991, p. 95

    Google Scholar 

  42. Friedrich Schlegel Ideaspara. 146 in Firchow, op. cit., p. 108

    Google Scholar 

  43. AM, p. 163

    Google Scholar 

  44. AM, p. 104. On the difference between the moral and religious viewpoints, see also Nishida's remarks on Kierkegaard in NRWV, p. 96. (The reception of Kierkegaard in Japan, and the reasons for it, is a subject of considerable interest in its own right. A good starting point is Masugata Kinya Kierkegaard's Reception in Japan, Memoirs of Osaka Kyoiku University, series 1, v. 38, no. 1, 1989, pp. 49–65, in which Nishida's reaction to Kierkegaard's thought, together with that of many other Japanese, is summarized)

    Google Scholar 

  45. IRSC, p. 153

    Google Scholar 

  46. IRSC, p. 151

    Google Scholar 

  47. NRWV, p. 93

    Google Scholar 

  48. IRSC, p. 27

    Google Scholar 

  49. IRSC, p. 48

    Google Scholar 

  50. I have developed this idea at more length in an essay East is East and West is Westin Cristina Chimisso (ed.) Exploring European Identities, Milton Keynes, UK: The Open University, 2003, pp. 230–262

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer Science + Business Media B.V

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wilkinson, R. (2009). Nishida, Aesthetics, and the Limits of Cultural Synthesis. In: Van den Braembussche, A., Kimmerle, H., Note, N. (eds) Intercultural Aesthetics. Einstein Meets Margritte: An Interdisciplinary Reflection on Science, Nature, Art, Human Action and Society, vol 9. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-5780-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics