Skip to main content
Log in

Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The enactive approach offers a distinctive view of how mental life relates to bodily activity at three levels: bodily self-regulation, sensorimotor coupling, and intersubjective interaction. This paper concentrates on the second level of sensorimotor coupling. An account is given of how the subjectively lived body and the living body of the organism are related (the body-body problem) via dynamic sensorimotor activity, and it is shown how this account helps to bridge the explanatory gap between consciousness and the brain. Arguments by O'Regan, Noë, and Myin that seek to account for the phenomenal character of perceptual consciousness in terms of ‘bodiliness’ and ‘grabbiness’ are considered. It is suggested that their account does not pay sufficient attention to two other key aspects of perceptual phenomenality: the autonomous nature of the experiencing self or agent, and the pre-reflective nature of bodily self-consciousness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bermúdez, J. L. 1998. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Bitbol, M. and Luisi, P.L. 2005. Autopoiesis with or without cognition: Defining life at its edge. Journal of the Royal Society Interface 1: 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 1997. On a confusion about a function of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates (pp. 375–416). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourgine, P. and Stewart, J. 2004. Autopoiesis and cognition. Artificial Life 20: 327–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, J. 1997. Fallacies or analyses? In N. Block, O. Flanagan and G. Güzeldere eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates (pp. 425–426). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. 1994. The Astonishing Hypothesis. The Scientific Search for the Soul. New York: Scribners.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derryberry, D. and Tucker, D. M. 1994. Motivating the focus of attention. In P.M. Niedenthal and S. Kitayama (eds.), The Heart's Eye: Emotional Influences in Perception and Attention, (pp. 167–196). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. 2005. Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, this volume.

  • Gallagher, S. 1986a. Lived body and environment. Research in Phenomenology 16: 139–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 1986b. Body image and body schema: A conceptual clarification. The Journal of Mind and Behavior 7: 541–554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2003. Bodily self-awareness and object perception. Theoria et Historia Scientarium: International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies 7: 53–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J.J. 1979. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. and Thompson, E. 2003. The mind-body-body problem. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum: International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies 7.

  • Humphrey, N. 2000. How to solve the mind-body problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 4: 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S.L. 1998. Consciousness in Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S.L. and Noë, A. 2003. Neural plasticity and consciousness. Biology and Philosophy 18: 131–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1960. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. Trans. Dorian Cairns. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. 1989. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenological Philosophy and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, Second Book. Trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. 2001. Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis. Lectures on Transcendental Logic. Trans. A.J. Steinbock. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Kriegel, U. 2003a. Consciousness as sensory quality and as implicit self-awareness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 2: 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. 2003b. Consciousness as intransitive self-consciousness: two views and an argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33: 103–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J. 2002. Synaptic Self. How Our Brains Become Who We Are. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. 2003. How not to find the neural signature of self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 12: 544–546.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (in press). The bodily self: the sensori-motor roots of pre-reflexive selfconsciousness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences.

  • Maturana, H.R. 1969. The neurophysiology of cognition. In P. Garvin (ed.), Cognition: A Multiple View, pp. 3–23. New York: Spartan Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H.R. 1970. Biology of cognition. In H.R. Maturana and F.J. Varela, Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living, (pp. 2–58). Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 43. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Maturana, H. R. and Varela, F. J. 1980. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 42. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H.R. and Varela, F.J. 1987. The Tree of Knowledge. The Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Boston: Shambala Press/New Science Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. 1962. Phenomenology of Perception. Trans Colin Smith. London: Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. 1964. Signs. Trans. Richard C. McCleary. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

  • Myin, E. and O'Regan, J.K. 2002. Perceptual consciousness, access to modality, and skill theories: A way to naturalize phenomenology? Journal of Consciousness Studies 9: 27–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83: 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2002. Is perspectival self-consciousness non-conceptual? Philosophical Quarterly 52: 185–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2004. Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. and Thompson, E. 2004a. Are there neural correlates of consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 3–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. and Thompson, E. 2004b. Sorting out the neural basis of consciousness. Authors' Reply to commentators. Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 87–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Regan, J.K. and Noë, A. 2001a. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24: 939–1011.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Regan, J.K. and Noë, A. 2001b. Authors' response: Acting out our sensory experience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24: 1011–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O'Regan, J.K., Myin, E. and Noë, A. 2005. Sensory consciousness explained (better) in terms of ‘corporality’ and ‘alerting capacity’. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, this volume.

  • Priest, S. 1998. Merleau-Ponty. London: Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. 1999. The Primacy of Movement. Amsterdam and Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. 1968. Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy 65: 55–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. 1984. Identity, Cause and Mind. Philosophical Essays. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. 2001. Empathy and consciousness. In E. Thompson (ed.), Between Ourselves: Second-Person Issues in the Study of Consciousness, Thorverton, UK: Imprint Academic. Also published in Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 (2001): 1–32.

  • Thompson, E. 2004. Life and mind: From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3: 381–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. 2005. Empathy and human experience. In J.D. Proctor (ed.), Science, Religion, and the Human Experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. and Varela, F.J. 2001. Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5: 418–425.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., Palacios, A., and Varela, F.J. 1992. Ways of coloring: Comparative color vision as a case study for cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15: 1–74. Reprinted in Alva Noë and Evan Thompson (eds.), Vision and Mind: Readings in the Philosophy of Perception. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2002.

  • Varela, F.J. 1979. Principles of Biological Autonomy. New York: Elsevier North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1991. Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. Tauber (ed.), Organism and the Origin of Self (pp. 79–107). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1997. Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition 34: 72–87.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. and Bourgine, P. (eds.) 1991. Toward a Practice of Autonomous Systems. Proceedings of the First European Conference on Artificial Life (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Varela, F.J. and Thompson, E. 2003. Neural synchrony and the unity of mind: A neurophenomenological perspective. In A. Cleeremans (ed.), The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration and Dissociation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J., Thompson, E. and Rosch, E. 1991. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Uexk!üll, J. 1957. A stroll through the worlds of animals and men. In K.S. Lashley (ed.), Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a Modern Concept (pp. 5–80). New York: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 1999. Self-Awareness and Alterity. A Phenomenological Investigation. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2002. First-person thoughts and embodied self-awareness: Some reflections on the relation between recent analytical philosophy and phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 7–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2003. Husserl's Phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2004. Intentionality and phenomenality: A phenomenological take on the hard problem. In E. Thompson (ed.), The Problem of Consciousness: New Essays in Phenomenological Philosophy of Mind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Evan Thompson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Thompson, E. Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenom Cogn Sci 4, 407–427 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-9003-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-9003-x

Keywords

Navigation