Skip to main content
Log in

Vulnerable Populations in Research: The Case of the Seriously Ill

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper advances a new criterion of a vulnerable population in research. According to this criterion, there are consent-based and fairness-based reasons for calling a group vulnerable. The criterion is then applied to the case of people with serious illnesses. It is argued that people with serious illnesses meet this criterion for reasons related to consent. Seriously ill people have a susceptibility to “enticing offers” that hold out the prospect of removing or alleviating illness, and this susceptibility reduces their ability to safeguard their own interests. This explains the inclusion of people with serious illnesses in the Belmont Report’s list of populations needing special protections, and supports the claim that vulnerability is the rule, rather than the exception, in biomedical research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Applebaum P., Roth L., Lidz C., Benson P., Winslade W. (1987) False Hopes and Best Data: Consent to Research and the Therapeutic Misconception. Hastings Center Report 17(2):20–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp T., Jennings B., Kinney E., Levine R. (2002). Pharmaceutical Research Involving the Homeless. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 27(5):547–564

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brody B.A. (1998). Research on the Vulnerable Sick. In: Kahn J.P., Mastroianni A.C., Sugarman J. (eds), Beyond Consent: Seeking Justice in Research. New York, Oxford University Press, pp. 32–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Dekkers W.J.M. (2001). Autonomy and dependence: Chronic physical illness and decision-making capacity. Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy 4:185–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckstein Sue. (2003). Research Involving Vulnerable Participants: Some Ethical Issues. In: Eckstein Sue (eds), Manual for Research Ethics Committees 6th ed. Cambridge, England, Cambridge University Press, pp. 105–109

    Google Scholar 

  • Englehardt H.T. Jr. (1984). Clinical Problems and the Concept of Disease. In: Nordenfelt L., Lindahl B., Ingemar B. (eds), Health, Disease, and Causal Explanation in Medicine. Philosophy and Medicine series vol 16. Dordrecht, D. Reidel, pp. 27–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Jennings, Bruce; Callahan, Daniel; and Caplan, Arthur. “Ethical Challenges of Chronic Illness.” Hastings Center Report 18, (1) (1988): Special Supplement 1–16

  • Kipnis, Kenneth. “Vulnerability in Research Subjects: A Bioethical Taxonomy.” In Ethical and Policy Issues in Research Involving Human Research Participants. Bethesda, MD: National Bioethics Advisory Commision, 2001: G1–G12

  • Kipnis K. (2003) Seven Vulnerabilities in the Pediatric Research Subject. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24:107–120

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine C. (2004). The Concept of Vulnerability in Disaster Research. Journal of Traumatic Stress 17(5):395–402

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine C., Faden R., Grady C., Hammerschmidt D., Eckenwiler L., Sugarman J. (2004). The Limitations of ’Vulnerability’ as a Protection for Human Research Participants. American Journal of Bioethics 4:44–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine C., Faden R., Grady C., Hammerschmidt D., Eckenwiler L., Sugarman J. (2004). Special Scrutiny: A Targeted Form of Research Protocol Review. Annals of Internal Medicine 140:220–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Lidz C.W., Appelbaum P.S., Grisso T., Renaud M. (2004). Therapeutic misconception and the appreciation of risks in clinical trials. Social Science and Medicine 58:1689–1697

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macintyre A. (1999). Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Chicago and La, Salle Illinois, Open Court

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele A.R. (2001) Autonomous Agents: From Self-Control to Autonomy. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller F.G., Brody H. (2003). A Critique of Clinical Equipoise. Hastings Center Report 33(3):19–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The Belmont Report . Available at the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services Website, <http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/belmont.htm> Original report published1979.

  • Nordenfelt L. (1987) On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Approach Philosophy and Medicine series, vol 26. Dordrecht, D. Reidel

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratzan R.M. (2000). ‘Being Old Makes You Different’: The Ethics of Research with Elderly Subjects. In: Boetzkes E., Waluchow W.J. (eds), Readings in Health Care Ethics. New York, USA, Broadview Press, pp. 454–468

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J. (1999). Collected Papers. Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J. (2001). Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge Mass, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson H.S., Belsky L. (2004). The Ancillary-Care Responsibilities of Medical Researchers. Hastings Center Report 34(1):25–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose S.L., Pietri C.E. (2002). Workers as Research Subjects: A Vulnerable Population. Journal of Occupational and Environmental Medicine 44(9):801–805

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider C. (1998). The Practice of Autonomy. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Shamoo A.E., Resnik D. (2003). Responsible Conduct of Research. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson J.J. (1990). The Realm of Rights. Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • U.S. Code of Federal Regulations. Title 45, Part 46. Available at <http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/45cfr46.htm>.

  • Wendler D. (2005) Protecting Subjects Who Cannot Give Consent: Toward a Better Standard for “Minimal” Risks. Hastings Center Report 35(5):37–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Medical Association. Declaration of Helsinki. October 2000. Available at <http://www.wma.net/e/policy/b3.htm>.

  • Zion D., Gilliam L., Loff B. (2000). The Declaration of Helsinki, CIOMS and the ethics of research on vulnerable populations. Nature Medicine 6(6):615–617

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philip J. Nickel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nickel, P.J. Vulnerable Populations in Research: The Case of the Seriously Ill. Theor Med Bioeth 27, 245–264 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-006-9000-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-006-9000-2

Keywords

Navigation